BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you consider making a contribution?

No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!



BAILII [Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback]

The Law Commission


You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> The Law Commission >> Homicide: Murder, Manslaughter And Infanticide (Report) [2006] EWLC 304(6) (28 November 2006)
URL: http://www.bailii.org/ew/other/EWLC/2006/304(6).html
Cite as: [2006] EWLC 304(6)

[New search] [Help]


    PART 6
    DURESS
    INTRODUCTION

    6.1      Consultees were more divided on duress as a defence to murder and attempted murder than on any other aspect of our review. There was a general consensus that duress should be, in some form, capable of being a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder. Accordingly, we do not intend to rehearse the reasons set out in the CP[1] for and against extending the defence to those offences.

    6.2      Opinion was divided as to whether duress should be a full or a partial defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder. We are very grateful to consultees for the quality of their arguments. Reasonable arguments have been deployed in support of each position.

    6.3      We believe that there are five main options.

    (1) Duress should be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder.
    (2) Duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder resulting in a conviction for second degree murder and a full defence to second degree murder and attempted murder.
    (3) Duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder resulting in a conviction for second degree murder and a partial defence to second degree murder resulting in a conviction for manslaughter.
    (4) Duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder and second degree murder, in each case resulting in a conviction for manslaughter.
    (5) Duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder but not a defence to second degree murder or attempted murder.
    We are recommending option (1).

    6.4      We are conscious that in recommending option (1), we are departing from our provisional proposal, namely that duress should be only a partial defence to first degree murder. We will be advancing our reasons for doing so but we begin by providing a brief outline of the current law relating to the defence of duress. We do so in order to emphasise the stringent requirements of the defence at common law. Having done so, we will explain why we are not attracted to options (2) to (5) above. We will then focus on our reasons for recommending option (1).

    THE CURRENT LAW

    6.5      Duress, if raised by admissible evidence and not disproved by the prosecution, is a full defence to all crimes except murder,[2] attempted murder,[3] possibly some forms of treason and, possibly, conspiracy.[4] The prevailing judicial view is that duress operates as an excuse rather than a justification.[5]

    6.6      There are two forms of duress: duress by threats and duress of circumstances.[6] The issue of whether duress should be a defence to murder has been discussed primarily in relation to duress by threats.[7] Duress by threats is where a person is told "commit a criminal offence or else you (or someone else) will be killed or seriously injured". The threat emanates from another person.

    6.7      By contrast, duress of circumstances is where a person commits an offence in response to a threat of death or serious harm that is not the result of being told "commit it or else".[8] An example is provided by the famous case of Dudley and Stephens.[9] Two shipwrecked sailors, threatened with death by starvation, killed and fed on a cabin boy who was shipwrecked with them.

    6.8      The general principles that govern duress by threats were set out by the Court of Appeal in Graham[10] and subsequently approved by the House of Lords in Howe.[11] In Graham, Lord Chief Justice Lane said that in law a person acts under duress by threats if the answers to the two following questions are "yes" and "no" respectively:

    (1) Was [D], or may [D] have been, impelled to act as he did because, as a result of what he reasonably believed [X] had said or done, he had good cause to fear that if he did not so act [X] would kill him or (if this is to be added)[12] cause him serious physical injury?
    (2) If so, have the prosecution made the jury sure that a sober person of reasonable firmness, sharing the characteristics of the defendant, would not have responded to whatever he reasonably believed [X] said or did by taking part in the killing? [13] ("the objective limb of the defence")
    The general principles that govern duress of circumstances are substantially the same.

    6.9      A feature of the defence, reinforced by the recent decision of the House of Lords in Z,[14] is its very stringent qualifying conditions,[15] namely:

    (1) the threat must be one of death or serious physical harm;[16]
    (2) the threat must be extraneous to the defendant;[17]
    (3) the threat must be directed at the defendant, a member of his or her immediate family or someone for whose safety the defendant reasonably regards him or herself as responsible;[18]
    (4) although there does not have to be a threat in fact,[19] the defendant must believe in the existence of a threat and his or her belief must be reasonable. Further, the defendant must reasonably believe that the threat will be implemented;[20]
    (5) although the threat need not be the sole motive for the defendant committing the principal offence, the defence is not available if the prosecution can prove that the defendant would have committed the offence even if the threat had not been made;
    (6) there must be no evasive action that the defendant can reasonably be expected to take (generally the defendant must reasonably believe the threat to be immediate or almost immediate); and[21]
    (7) the defendant must not have voluntarily laid him or herself open to the duress. In particular, if the defendant voluntarily associates with those engaged in criminal activity where he is aware or ought to be aware[22] that he or she may be subject to any compulsion by threats of serious violence, the defendant cannot rely on duress as a defence to any act which he or she is thereafter compelled to do.

    6.10      In addition to these qualifying conditions the defence involves an evaluative condition (the objective limb of the defence) that must also be satisfied. The defence is not available if no reasonable person, sharing the defendant's ("D's") characteristics, would have responded to the threat by committing the principal offence. In Bowen,[23] the Court of Appeal said that relevant characteristics include age, (possibly) sex, pregnancy, serious physical disability and "recognised mental illness or psychiatric condition". Characteristics due to self-induced abuse, whether through alcohol or drugs, are not relevant characteristics and neither is being unusually pliant or timid.[24]

    6.11      In Z,[25] Lord Bingham expressed the prevailing judicial attitude to the defence:

    … I find it unsurprising that the law in this and other jurisdictions should have been developed so as to confine the defence of duress within narrowly defined limits.[26]
    Our provisional proposals and questions

    6.12      In the CP, we provisionally proposed that duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder, reducing the offence to second degree murder.[27]

    6.13      We asked whether duress should be a defence to second degree murder and attempted murder and, if so, whether it should be a full or partial defence.

    6.14      We provisionally proposed that for a plea of duress to succeed as a partial defence to first degree murder (and to second degree murder and attempted murder were the defence to apply to those offences), the threat must have been one of death or life-threatening harm.[28]

    6.15      In respect of children and young people, we invited views as to whether duress, if successfully pleaded as a defence to first degree murder, should give rise to more lenient treatment than in the case of adults.[29]

    6.16      In addition, we made the following firm proposals:

    (1) In deciding whether a person of reasonable firmness might have acted as D did, the jury should be able to take into account all the circumstances of D, including his or her age, other than those that bear upon his or her capacity to withstand duress.
    (2) D's belief as to the existence of the threat and its being implemented must be not only honestly but also reasonably held.[30]
    Responses to the provisional proposals and questions

    6.17      A very substantial majority of those who addressed the issue thought that duress should be a defence to first degree murder. However, opinion was divided as to whether it should be a full or partial defence. A considerable, but not overwhelming, majority thought that it should be a partial defence. Of that majority, most felt that it should result in a conviction for second degree murder rather than manslaughter.

    6.18      A very substantial majority of those who addressed the issue thought that duress should be a defence to second degree murder and attempted murder. However, again, opinion was divided as to whether it should be a full defence. A slight majority thought that it should be a full defence.

    6.19      A large majority of those who addressed the issue thought that for duress to be a defence to first degree murder, the threat must be one of death or life-threatening harm.

    6.20      A large majority of those who addressed the issue agreed that duress if successfully pleaded by a child or young person as a defence to first degree murder should result in more lenient treatment than it would for adults.

    OUR RECOMMENDATIONS

    6.21      We recommend that:

    (1) duress should be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder.
    (2) For duress to be a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, the threat must be one of death or life-threatening harm.
    (3) The defendant should bear the legal burden of proving the qualifying conditions of the defence on a balance of probabilities.
    OPTIONS THAT WE REJECT
    Option (2): duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder resulting in a conviction for second degree murder but a full defence to second degree murder and attempted murder

    6.22      This option reflects the view of the majority of consultees who addressed the issue. It avoids the 'all or nothing' outcome that results from duress being a full defence to first degree murder. Accordingly, it addresses the concerns of those who believe that a stark choice between conviction for first degree murder, on the one hand, and an acquittal, on the other hand, will be prone to produce the 'wrong result'. On this view, a mandatory life sentence would be too harsh for a parent who played a minor role as a secondary party in a killing when faced with a threat to the life of his or her child. Conversely, an acquittal would be too generous in the case of D who, in order to preserve his or her own life, intentionally kills an innocent person.

    6.23      In addition, it might be thought that an advantage of the option, at least in relation to first degree murder, is that it accords with our recommendations for provocation and diminished responsibility, namely that they reduce first degree murder to second degree murder.

    6.24      We recognise the attraction of the option in the way that it seeks to accommodate the very broad range of circumstances in which duress can operate in cases of intentional killing. However, if the option were to be adopted, there would be a vast difference in the outcome depending on whether or not it was established that D had the requisite fault element for first degree murder. If it were proved that D had the mental element for first degree murder, a successful plea of duress would result in a conviction for second degree murder. By contrast, if the prosecution were unable to prove that D had that mental element, a successful plea of duress would result in exoneration. Accordingly, we envisage that, were the option to be adopted, in many cases it would be submitted that D did not intend to kill but merely intended to do no more than was necessary in order to ensure he or she or another would not be killed. This would be to confuse intention and motive and, no doubt, the trial judge would direct a jury to distinguish the two. However, there would be a real danger that a sympathetic jury would confuse the two and conclude that the purpose of D doing what he or

    she did was to save rather than take life.[31]

    6.25      In addition, the indulgence of trying to persuade the jury to substitute motive for intention, while available to the principal offender, would be denied to some secondary parties. It would not be available to secondary parties who were charged with first degree murder not on the basis that they intended to kill but on the basis that they had foreseen the risk of the principal offender committing first degree murder.[32] For example, D1 and D2 are threatened with death unless they assist a gang of burglars to commit a burglary. D1 and D2 both anticipate that their role will be confined to driving members of the gang to the house where the burglary will be committed and keep watch. D1, but not D2, anticipates that, should the householder disturb the gang, the gang will intentionally kill the householder. On arriving at the house, D1 is ordered to stay in the car and keep watch. D2 is told to accompany the gang into the house. The householder does disturb the gang one of whom tells D2 to stab the householder several times in the chest. D2 does so believing that he will be shot unless he does so. Whereas D2 may seek to persuade a jury that he did not intend to kill, D1 will not be able to deny the fault element that makes him guilty of first degree murder as a secondary party, namely that he foresaw that the householder might be intentionally killed.

    6.26      Were this option to be adopted, it could also be argued that an anomalous position with regard to attempted murder would be created:

    D, under duress, shoots both V1 and V2 with intent to kill, killing V1 but not V2.

    6.27      In relation to the killing of both V1 and V2, under the current law D has no defence of duress. Under our recommendation, D would be able to plead duress as a complete defence to both the murder of V1 and the attempted murder of V2. By way of contrast, under option (2) D would have a partial defence of duress in relation to the killing of V1 but a full defence in relation to the attempted killing of V2. The element of chance in whether the full defence is or is not available, depending on whether D is successful in carrying out his instructions, makes this option an unattractive one.

    6.28      These considerations militate against recommending this option. In addition, for the reasons that we set out below,[33] we believe as a matter of principle that duress ought to be a complete rather than a partial defence not only to second degree murder but also to first degree murder.

    Option (3): duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder resulting in a conviction for second degree murder and a partial defence to second degree murder resulting in a conviction for manslaughter

    6.29      This option has the same advantages as option (2) as far as duress being a partial defence to first degree murder is concerned. Further, by making duress a partial but not a full defence to second degree murder, it dilutes, without wholly removing, the disadvantages that we have highlighted in connection with option (2).

    6.30      However, the option is inconsistent with the overall structural approach that we are recommending. In Part 2 above, we explained why we believe that provocation and diminished responsibility should be partial defences to first degree murder but not to second degree murder. If we were to recommend that duress should be a partial defence to second degree murder, the question would arise: why not do the same with provocation and diminished responsibility? In truth, if we believed that duress should be a partial defence to both first degree murder and second degree murder, then it would be difficult to justify a position under which provocation and diminished responsibility are not partial defences to second degree murder. However, as we explain below, we believe that there are valid reasons why duress, on the one hand, should be a complete defence to first degree murder and provocation and diminished responsibility, on the other hand, should be partial defences.

    6.31      A further difficulty with this option is that it provides no principled basis on which to decide whether duress should or should not be a defence to attempted murder.

    Option (4): duress should be a partial defence to both first degree murder and second degree murder, in each case resulting in a conviction for manslaughter

    6.32      Similar, if not identical, considerations apply as in option (3) above.

    Option (5): duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder but not a defence to second degree murder or attempted murder

    6.33      Some consultees, while of the view that duress should be a partial defence to first degree murder, argued that duress should not be a defence to second degree murder or attempted murder. This was because there would be sufficient flexibility in the discretionary life sentence for second degree murder to accurately reflect any mitigation arising from duress.[34]

    This option would be consistent with our recommendations in relation to the partial defences of provocation and diminished responsibility. However, the option has to be evaluated in the light of the fact that duress operates as a full defence to all offences to which under the present law it is capable of being a defence.

    6.34      As under option (2), it is arguable that an anomaly arises with the treatment of attempted murder.[35] It becomes a matter of chance whether D has a partial defence or no defence at all.

    6.35      Here is another example illustrating how option (5) would operate less than satisfactorily. D, under duress, attacks three people V1, V2 and V3. D intends to kill V1 and does so. D intends to cause serious harm to V2 and V3. V2 dies but V3 survives. D would be guilty of second degree murder in relation to V1. D is also guilty of second degree murder in relation to V2. D is acquitted of causing grievous bodily harm with intent to V3.[36] We do not consider this to be a satisfactory outcome.

    THE OPTION THAT WE ARE RECOMMENDING
    Option (1): duress should be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder
    A full defence to first degree murder

    6.36      We acknowledge that the majority of consultees who favoured duress being a defence to first degree murder agreed with our provisional proposal that it should be a partial rather than a full defence to first degree murder. At the same time, a significant minority[37] thought that it should be a full defence and, on balance, we are now persuaded that it should be.

    6.37      Previously, the Commission has recommended that duress should be a full rather than a partial defence to murder:

    … where the duress is so compelling that the defendant could not reasonably have been expected to resist it, perhaps being a threat not to the defendant himself but to an innocent hostage dear to him, it would be … unjust that the defendant should suffer the stigma of a conviction even for manslaughter. We do not think that any social purpose is served by requiring the law to prescribe such standards of determination and heroism.[38]

    6.38      In the CP, we provisionally proposed a different approach in relation to first degree murder. There were two main reasons:

    (1) we thought it important that there should be consistency with the partial defences of provocation and diminished responsibility, both of which we were proposing should reduce first degree murder to second degree murder;
    (2) it would not be right for a person who had intentionally killed to be completely exonerated.
    REASONS FOR QUESTIONING OUR PROVISIONAL PROPOSAL THAT DURESS SHOULD BE A PARTIAL DEFENCE TO FIRST DEGREE MURDER

    6.39      We now believe that, in this context, we exaggerated the importance of treating duress in a manner that was consistent with the way provocation and diminished responsibility fitted into our proposed structure.[39] Professor Ormerod commented:

    … I am not convinced that duress has been shown to be sufficiently similar to provocation and diminished responsibility to warrant like treatment. An argument could be made that it ought to be treated like self defence, and therefore ought to afford a complete defence. In truth, the defence is distinct from all of the others. It has a strong objective element which allies it with provocation, and it focuses on external pressures triggering a response, but it is a defence in which D has made a more calculated choice. Similarly, with diminished responsibility, the defences might be regarded as excuses (whatever that may mean), but duress is very different from the quasi-medicalised defence (unless we are treating them both as some form of diminished capacity defence).

    6.40      We also acknowledge that we exaggerated the strength of the case for duress being a partial defence to first degree murder merely because, under our proposals, there would be more categories of murder. We now accept that, while having more categories of murder may make it easier to effect a compromise between competing views, the mere fact that there are more categories of murder does not assist in deciding whether or not as a matter of principle duress should be a full defence to first degree murder.

    6.41      In the CP, we stressed that if D intentionally kills he or she deserves to be stigmatised despite killing under duress. However, we now believe that we paid insufficient attention to the fact that, for the defence to succeed, D must satisfy the very stringent requirements of the defence including satisfying a jury that a reasonable person, sharing his or her characteristics, might have acted in the way that D did.

    6.42      Further, during the consultation process it became clear that significant anomalies might arise were duress to be a partial defence to some homicide offences but a full defence (or no defence) to others. It is hard, for example, to see why duress should be a full defence (or no defence) to attempted murder but a partial defence to first degree murder, given that only chance may distinguish whether the one offence or the other has been committed. While it might not be impossible to find a justification in relation to each individual offence, the overall structure threatens to become incoherent.

    REASONS FOR CONCLUDING THAT DURESS SHOULD BE A FULL DEFENCE TO FIRST DEGREE MURDER

    6.43      The argument that duress should be a full defence to first degree murder has a moral basis. It is that the law should not stigmatise a person who, on the basis of a genuine and reasonably held belief, intentionally killed in fear of death or life- threatening injury in circumstances where a jury is satisfied that an ordinary person of reasonable fortitude might have acted in the same way. If a reasonable person might have acted as D did, then the argument for withholding a complete defence is undermined. In the words of Professor Ormerod, "if the jury find that the defendant has, within the terms of the defence, acted reasonably, it seems unfair to treat him as a second degree murderer or even a manslaughterer".

    6.44      Further, the option also accords with the way that duress operates as a complete defence in relation to other offences and it is, therefore, conducive to coherence and consistency as we pointed out above.

    6.45      One respondent who favoured duress being a partial defence to first degree murder did so because he thought that this was the best way of accommodating each side in the moral debate. We see the force of this argument. However, we believe that if the arguments of principle and morality point decidedly in one direction, our recommendation should reflect what we believe to be a principled approach rather than one based on a desire to accommodate the different viewpoints.

    6.46      An important counter-argument is that the law rightly attaches special sanctity to innocent human life and that this should preclude duress ever being a full defence to first degree murder.[40] We now depart from this view, in so far as we believe that the 'sanctity of life' argument was not meant to deal with examples such as ten year olds or peripheral secondary parties becoming involved in killing under duress. The 'sanctity of life' argument may be more confusing than illuminating in this context.

    6.47      Those who are opposed to duress being a full defence to first degree murder argue that cases of intentional killing under duress can never be completely deserving of excuse, but some are more deserving of excuse than others. For that reason, so the argument runs, duress should result in a conviction of second degree murder where the sentence can reflect the circumstances of each case.

    6.48      Of course, views may differ as to what makes a case more or less deserving of excuse. For example, some, but not all, will think that a person is more deserving of excuse if he or she commits first degree murder under duress in order to secure a net gain of life.[41] Alternatively, some will believe that those who commit

    first degree murder under duress in order to save the life of an innocent third party are more deserving of excuse than those who do so to save themselves, particularly if the killing also secures a net gain of life. Others will point to the case of a secondary party such as a taxi driver who is threatened with death unless he or she drives a gang to a location where he or she knows they are intending to kill a householder.

    6.49      By contrast, others will point to the case of a drug addict who, threatened by his or her supplier to whom he or she is in debt, commits a murder to placate his or her supplier to whom he or she owes money.

    6.50      Although, amongst those who would prefer duress to be a partial defence to first degree murder, there may not be unanimity as to what makes a case more (or less) deserving, they are as one in stressing the range of circumstances in which duress may be pleaded. In their view, what is required is a flexible sentencing regime which, while recognising that a person who intentionally kills under duress ought always to be stigmatised, allows the trial judge to pass a suitably severe or lenient sentence depending on the circumstances.

    6.51      We see the attraction of this view. However, we believe that there is more force in the views expressed by consultees who believe that duress should be a complete defence to first degree murder. For example, the Criminal Bar Association argued that, if duress were not a complete defence to first degree murder, it would give the impression that, in law, "it is better to prevent the death of a stranger than to prevent the death of one's children." Similarly, Mr Justice Elias said that withholding duress as a complete defence implies that the criminal law should support the view that "people ought to act in an exceptionally moral and courageous way. They are being punished for giving way to what will often be enormous fear and wholly understandable human frailty."

    6.52      We also think it important to bear in mind the stringent qualifying conditions that attach to the defence. In particular, the majority of the House of Lords in Z[42] were firmly of the view that the defence ought not to be available to D if he or she saw or ought to have foreseen the risk of being subjected to any compulsion by threats of violence. We believe that this will serve to exclude the most unmeritorious cases where the defence should simply not be available. It is true that it will not in itself exclude all undeserving cases but we believe that juries should be trusted not to accept the defence in undeserving cases.

    6.53      Above all, we believe that it is essential to recognise and accord proper weight to the fact that for the defence to succeed, a jury must form a judgement that a reasonable person in D's position might have committed first degree murder. If a jury forms that judgement, we believe that D should be completely exonerated despite having intentionally killed.

    Distinguishing cases according to whether or not the defendant acted in response to a threat against his or her own person

    6.54      We have considered whether it would be appropriate to distinguish cases of duress according to whether D has intentionally killed in order to save the life of an innocent third party as opposed to his or her own life. Some believe that there is a clear moral difference between acting on a threat directed at another and acting on a threat directed at oneself. However, we believe that it would be unsatisfactory to recommend reform based on such a distinction.

    6.55      Consider these examples. A child is threatened with life-threatening harm by his or her psychopathic father unless he or she helps him to perpetrate a murder. A pregnant woman is threatened with death unless she kills V. She yields to the threat in order to safeguard the life of her unborn baby who, while in the womb, has no legal recognition for the purposes of the criminal law, apart from the offences of child destruction[43], attempting to procure a miscarriage[44] and offences under the Abortion Act 1967. An uncle threatened with death commits murder in order to preserve his own life so that he can donate a kidney to his desperately ill nephew. In our view, it would be wrong to deny such persons a complete defence merely because they acted in order to preserve their own lives.

    Distinguishing between principal offenders and secondary parties

    6.56      We have also considered whether it would be appropriate to distinguish cases depending on whether D was a principal offender or a secondary party. At one stage, we were inclined to do so. However, for two reasons, we believe that it would be undesirable.

    6.57      First, it assumes, wrongly, that a secondary party acting under duress is necessarily less culpable than a principal offender acting under duress. For example, a husband and his wife are told that their child will be killed unless they kill V who is the husband's brother. They agree that the wife will perpetrate the killing and the husband will keep watch. It would be wrong to afford the husband but not the wife a complete defence. Likewise, a psychopathic father threatens his child with serious physical harm unless the child commits a murder while the father keeps watch. We believe that, unhesitatingly, most people would brand the father as the more culpable. The jury should be trusted to employ the objective test to distinguish deserving from undeserving cases, without this added legal complication.

    6.58      Further, it would put a premium on determining whether someone was a principal offender or a secondary party. For example, a husband and wife are threatened that their child will be killed unless they kill V. They decide to kill V by poisoning. Before V joins them for lunch, together they measure out a fatal dose of strychnine which the wife sprinkles over V's soup. V drinks the soup and dies. On one view, the wife is the principal offender because she is the most direct and immediate cause of V's death. Her husband is a secondary party. Suppose, however, that, in order to introduce the fatal dose into V's soup, the husband lifts V's soup bowl across the dining table and then, after the wife ladles out the soup, replaces the bowl. Alternatively, the husband's sole contribution is to pass a spoon to V.[45] We believe that to make the liability of the husband and wife dependent on whether or not one was a principal offender and the other a secondary party would result in liability being dependent on fine distinctions that would reflect poorly on the law, particularly where the issue is whether one or other, or both, is guilty of first degree murder.

    Consistency with provocation and diminished responsibility

    6.59      It might be thought that our recommendation is inconsistent with our recommendations that provocation and diminished responsibility should operate as no more than partial defences to first degree murder.

    6.60      On the assumption that provocation, diminished responsibility and duress are all defences that operate by way of excusing D, the way that the current law treats these defences is illogical. Provocation and diminished responsibility each has a weaker moral claim to excusatory status in the law of murder than duress. It is true that provocation is grounded on the view that D has lost his or her self-control whereas in cases of duress D has made a conscious, albeit an unwilling, choice. It is also true that in cases of diminished responsibility, D is partially excused because it is recognised that his or her responsibility for intentionally killing is lessened. However, in cases of provocation and diminished responsibility, D has not killed in order to preserve innocent life and yet he or she has a partial excuse. By contrast, a person who pleads duress is one who has sought to avoid the death of or serious physical harm[46] to an innocent person (not necessarily him or herself) by doing no more than is required to avert that harm. Yet, provocation and diminished responsibility excuse murder while duress does not.

    6.61      More importantly, it is inappropriate to characterise duress as an excusatory defence in the same way that provocation and diminished responsibility are excusatory. Although it cannot be said of all cases, some instances of duress come close to being a justification for killing rather than an excuse. To give an example of duress of circumstances, the roped climber who cuts the rope after his or her companion has accidentally slipped and is dragging them both to oblivion is a case in point. The same claim cannot be made in respect of either provocation or diminished responsibility. No act of killing comes close to being justified if committed solely in response to provocation or as a result of diminished responsibility. Viewed in this light, the case for distinguishing duress from provocation and diminished responsibility becomes more compelling.[47]

    6.62      The fact that we are recommending a reformulated partial defence of provocation does not detract from the above. It would be wrong to conclude that the reformulation, by removing the loss of self-control requirement and at the same time requiring that D must have a "justifiable sense of having been seriously wronged", places the defence on a justificatory basis. The first limb of the reformulation is seeking to do two things. First, it avoids the well known problems caused by the loss of self-control requirement.[48] Secondly, it is emphasising that the provocation must be of such gravity that if a person responds to it by intentionally killing, he or she merits being partially excused despite his or her conduct lacking any justification.

    6.63      The second limb of the reformulated partial defence of provocation focuses on an intentional killing in response to a fear of serious violence. At first blush, it might be thought that this places the defence on a more justificatory footing. However, it is important to emphasise that the defence comes into play only if the justificatory defence of self-defence is unavailable or unsuccessful. If self-defence is unavailable or unsuccessful it will be because D used an unreasonable amount of force in the circumstances. In such cases the D' conduct cannot be characterised as justified.

    6.64      In conclusion, we believe that the following extract from one of our earlier reports bears repetition. After setting out the arguments against a defence of duress to murder, we said:

    … the law should not insist upon condemning a person who acts under compulsion which he is unable to resist; that in doing so it would be making excessive demands on human nature and imposing penalties in circumstances where they are unjustified as retribution and irrelevant as a deterrent. The law must recognise that the instinct and perhaps the duty of self-preservation is powerful and natural, and that it would be 'censorious and inhumane if it did not recognise the appalling plight of a person who suddenly finds his life in jeopardy unless he submits and obeys'.[49] This argument is most cogently advanced by the majority in Lynch's case and convinces us that it would be quite unjust that a person who has committed an offence only because of threats which he could not withstand (subject to qualifications as to the nature of the threats) should face trial and conviction with the obloquy inherent therein.[50]

    6.65      We recommend that duress, if successfully pleaded, should be a full defence to first degree murder.

    A possible refinement of our recommendation

    6.66      Under our recommendation, duress would be a full defence to first degree murder if D satisfies the qualifying conditions[51] on a balance of probabilities and the jury concludes that a sober person of reasonable fortitude in the circumstances of D might have committed first degree murder.

    6.67      However, we envisage that in some cases, while D may be able to satisfy the qualifying conditions, the jury will conclude that no sober person of reasonable fortitude in the circumstances of D would have committed first degree murder. We believe that such cases are much more likely to arise if D is a principal offender as opposed to a secondary party.

    6.68      It would be possible to adopt an 'all or nothing' approach by virtue of which D would either be convicted of first degree murder or completely exonerated depending on whether or not he or she satisfies all the elements of the defence. However, that might be thought to be too severe on those who had proved that they genuinely and reasonably believed that they, or a person for whom they reasonably felt responsible, would be killed or very seriously harmed unless they committed first degree murder.

    6.69      In such cases, a conviction for second degree murder would recognise the perilous circumstances in which, without any fault on their part, they had (or reasonably thought they had) been placed while acknowledging that they ought to be convicted of a very serious offence because no reasonable person would have acted as they did.

    A full defence to second degree murder and attempted murder

    6.70      Since we are recommending that duress should be a full defence to first degree murder, it would be anomalous were we to recommend otherwise in relation to second degree murder and attempted murder.

    6.71      We recommend that duress, if successfully pleaded, should be a full defence to second degree murder and attempted murder.

    6.72      We believe that our recommendations that duress should be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder are conducive to achieving clarity and coherence. However, we have rejected other options not merely because we think that they are intellectually untidy. Ultimately, the function of the criminal law is not to produce intellectual tidiness for its own sake but, rather, to do practical justice as it would be seen by ordinary members of the public. We do not believe that the options that we have rejected would achieve that result. We believe that the recommendations we are making would do so.

    ADDITIONAL RECOMMENDATIONS
    Fear of death or life-threatening harm

    6.73      A large majority of consultees were in favour of the proposal that for duress to be a defence to murder or attempted murder, then the threat must be one of death or life-threatening harm.

    6.74      It is true that, under the current law, the defence can succeed if the threat was one of death or serious harm, whether or not life-threatening harm. However, we believe that the special harm involved or intended in cases of first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder justifies a higher threshold.

    6.75      We are conscious that some consultees have reservations about the threat having to be one of life-threatening harm. Some believe that it would exclude deserving cases such as a parent witnessing his or her child being tortured.[52] Others believe that the concept 'life-threatening' is too vague and ambiguous.[53] However, it is important to recognise that the threat does not have to be objectively life-threatening. It is the reasonableness of D's perception of the threat that is critical. D would have to prove that he or she honestly and reasonably believed that the nature of the threat was such that, if implemented, would involve a risk to life. The jury would be entitled to take into account the age and vulnerability of the person being threatened with harm. Thus, a jury might well conclude that D reasonably believed that a threat of torture to his or her five-year-old child involved a risk of life-threatening harm while taking a different view if the threat of torture was directed at the D's spouse.

    6.76      We recommend that for duress to be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, the threat must be one of death or life-threatening harm.

    Reasonably held belief

    6.77      We did not pose a direct question to consultees as to whether D's belief that a threat of death or life-threatening harm had been made and would be implemented had to be reasonably held. A few consultees questioned the need for the belief to be reasonably held. It was suggested that the requirement was unnecessary because a jury would be unlikely to conclude that an unreasonable belief was an honestly held belief.[54] One consultee thought that a reasonableness requirement would make it more difficult for children and the mentally vulnerable to make out the defence.[55]

    6.78      Previously the Law Commission has expressed support for the proposition that D's belief should only have to be honestly held.[56] Further, neither provocation nor self-defence import a test of reasonableness.[57] However, in this respect, there are important differences between duress, on the one hand, and provocation and self-defence, on the other hand. The defence of duress revolves around a threat of death or serious-harm that will materialise at some point in the future should D not do what he or she has been told to do. Typically, D will have time to reflect on and assess the nature and strength of the threat. As Professor Ormerod commented, "D has made a more calculated choice".

    6.79      By contrast, in cases of provocation and self-defence, typically there is a more immediate temporal or physical nexus between the actions of the victim ("V") and the action of D that is precipitated by the actions of V. In relation to self-defence, the law recognises this even in relation to that aspect of the defence – the degree of force used by D – where there is a reasonableness requirement. Thus, Lord Morris observed:

    If there has been an attack so that defence is reasonably necessary it will be recognised that a person cannot weigh to a nicety the exact measure of his necessary defensive action.[58]

    6.80      It is clear that at common law, D's belief in the existence of the threat and that it will be implemented must be reasonably held.[59] It would be anomalous that if D is pleading duress as a defence to theft his or her belief in the existence of the threat must be reasonably held but not if D is pleading duress as a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder or attempted murder.

    6.81      At the same time, we see no reason why the particular circumstances of D should not be capable of being taken into account in determining whether or not his or her belief was reasonably held. This would enable account to be taken of the age and vulnerability of D. It would also accord with the decision in Martin (David Paul).[60] The Court of Appeal held that expert testimony that D was suffering from a recognised psychiatric condition which made him more likely than others to regard things said or done as threatening and to believe that they would be carried out was admissible evidence. We do not believe that Z[61] casts doubt on that decision.

    6.82      Contrary to the view that we have previously expressed, we now believe that for duress to be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, the defendant's belief as to the existence of the threat and to its being implemented must be not only honestly held but also reasonably held.

    The defendant's characteristics for the purpose of the objective limb of the defence[62]

    6.83      Two consultees, Professor Ronnie Mackay and Nicola Padfield, disagreed with our proposal that the relevant characteristics should not include those which bear on D's capacity to withstand duress. Professor Mackay argued that to alter the common law rule in Bowen,[63] in which it was held that relevant characteristics include psychiatric syndromes and mental illnesses, would be unfair and is driven by a suggested need for consistency with provocation. Professor Mackay argues that the two pleas are very different in nature. Professor Mackay further argues that it is speculative to suggest that the decision in Attorney General for Jersey v Holley[64] will mean that Bowen will no longer be followed.

    6.84      Despite Professor Mackay and Nicola Padfield's objections, we believe that in deciding whether a person of reasonable firmness would have acted as D did in a case of first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, the jury should be able to take into account all of the circumstances of D, including his or her age, other than those which bear upon his or her capacity to withstand duress. This recommendation is consistent with our recommended reformulation of the partial defence of provocation.[65] We believe that it would be anomalous if there were to be a significant distinction between the characteristics that are relevant to provocation and duress.

    6.85      We appreciate that our recommendation, if implemented, would result in a narrower test for first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder than the Bowen test which would apply to all other offences. However, we consider that this is justified for two reasons. First, given the seriousness of the harm caused (or intended) in cases of first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, it is important that a strict objective standard is maintained to limit the scope of the defence. Secondly, unlike other offences, the partial defence of diminished responsibility would be available to mentally disordered persons charged with first degree murder. We acknowledge that, under our recommendations, diminished responsibility would not be available to those charged with second degree murder or attempted murder. However, since both these offences attract a discretionary life sentence, any mental disorder can be taken into account in sentencing.

    6.86      We believe that, in deciding whether a person of reasonable firmness might have acted as the defendant did, the jury should be able to take into account all the circumstances of the defendant, including his or her age but not any other characteristics which bear upon his or her capacity to withstand duress.

    A reverse burden of proof
    A further consultation

    6.87      Once it became clear that some consultees thought that duress should be a full defence to first degree, second degree and attempted murder, we considered the question of whether the burden of proof should be on D when pleading duress as a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder. As this was not a matter on which we had originally consulted, we conducted a further consultation amongst consultees who had indicated that they supported duress being either a full or a partial defence to first degree murder.

    THE FURTHER QUESTIONS THAT WE ASKED

    6.88      In relation to first degree murder, we asked whether consultees would prefer duress to be:

    (1) a full defence with the burden on the prosecution to disprove;
    (2) a full defence with the persuasive burden on D;
    (3) a partial defence with the burden on the prosecution to disprove; or
    (4) a partial defence with the persuasive burden on D.

    6.89      In relation to second degree murder we asked whether consultees would prefer duress to be:

    (1) a full defence;
    (2) a partial defence resulting in a conviction for manslaughter; or
    (3) no defence.

    6.90      We also asked whether the burden of proof should be the same for second degree murder as for first degree murder or different.

    6.91      In relation to Article 6(2) of the European Convention Human Rights (ECHR) we asked whether:

    (1) introducing a defence, but subject to a reverse burden, would interfere with the presumption of innocence;
    (2) if the answer to question one was "yes", imposing a reverse burden would pursue a legitimate aim; and
    (3) if the answer to question two was "yes", imposing a reverse legal burden would be a proportionate means of pursuing the aim.
    THE RESPONSES

    6.92      Only two consultees favoured duress being a full defence to first degree murder with the burden on the prosecution to disprove. Five consultees favoured it being a full defence to first degree murder with the persuasive burden on D. Six consultees favoured it being a partial defence to first degree murder with the burden on the prosecution to disprove. Three consultees favoured it being a partial defence to first degree murder with the persuasive burden on D.

    6.93      Five consultees favoured duress being a full defence to second degree murder with the burden on the prosecution to disprove. Three consultees favoured it being a full defence to second degree murder with the persuasive burden on D. Two consultees thought that it should be a partial defence to second degree murder with the burden on the prosecution to disprove. Four consultees thought that it should not be a defence to second degree murder.

    6.94      All the members of the judiciary who responded thought that, if the persuasive burden were placed on D in circumstances where duress was pleaded as a defence to first and second degree murder, it would not offend against article 6(2). By contrast, some academic consultees thought that a reverse burden would engage Article 6(2) and that, even if a reverse burden was pursuing a legitimate aim, it was not a proportionate means of pursuing that aim. One consultee was of the opinion that there were no compelling arguments for distinguishing murder from other offences in this regard.

    The objective limb of the defence

    6.95      In Graham,[66] Lord Lane said that the burden was on the prosecution to prove that a sober person of reasonable firmness would not have responded to the threat of death or serious harm by committing the offence with which D was charged. It might be thought that reversing the burden of proof would involve D having to prove that a sober person of reasonable firmness might have responded to the threat by committing first degree murder.

    6.96      However, unlike Lord Lane, we do not believe that it is helpful to speak in terms of a burden of proof in relation to the objective limb. This is because, in our view, the objective limb involves the jury undertaking "an exercise in judgment or evaluation, not the application of a burden of proof".[67] In determining the objective limb of the defence, the jury is making an assessment which is dependent upon judgement.[68] Accordingly, any recommendation that we make in relation to the burden of proof will be in relation to the qualifying conditions of the defence of duress and not in relation to the objective limb of the defence.

    Burden of proof and defences

    6.97      A principle of the common law is that the prosecution must prove the guilt of D.[69] At the very least, this means that the prosecution must prove beyond reasonable doubt that D satisfies all the definitional elements of the offence. In the context of murder, this means that the prosecution must prove that:

    (1) D did an act which caused the death of V; and
    (2) in doing the act, D intended to kill or cause or serious bodily harm to V.

    6.98      However, the law recognises that to convict a person of murder in every case where he or she intended to kill or cause serious harm would give rise to injustice. An example is where D kills V in circumstances where D was doing no more than responding to a potentially lethal attack on D by V. If so, D is entitled to plead a defence, namely that he or she was acting in self-defence.

    6.99      In cases where D alleges that he or she killed out of self-defence, the common law says that, provided that D discharges an evidential burden, the prosecution must prove beyond reasonable doubt that D, in killing V, was not acting in self-defence. D discharges the evidential burden if there is admissible evidence suggesting the possibility that D was acting in self-defence when he or she killed V.[70] In the way that it requires the prosecution to disprove self-defence as a defence to murder, the common law treats murder in exactly the same way as it does any other offence.

    6.100      Further, in the way that it requires the prosecution to disprove self-defence, the common law treats self-defence in the same way that it treats provocation and duress. The underlying principle, namely that the burden of proof is on the prosecution to disprove the defence, applies equally to all three defences. It might be thought, therefore, that were duress to be a full defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, D ought to have to discharge only an evidential burden.

    Reasons for departing from the common law principle
    THE PROBLEM OF DISPROVING DURESS

    6.101      We do not believe that the legal burden of proof should be on the prosecution to disprove duress as a defence to murder, with D only having to discharge an evidential burden, merely because that is the position when provocation and self-defence are raised as partial and full defences to murder respectively.

    6.102      There is an important difference between provocation and self-defence, on the one hand, and duress, on the other hand. Lord Bingham reflected this difference when he observed in Z that the defence of duress is "peculiarly difficult for the prosecution to investigate and disprove beyond reasonable doubt."[71] In doing so, Lord Bingham was echoing what we had said in an earlier report.[72]

    No analogy with provocation and self-defence

    6.103      As we pointed out in 1993, in many cases of provocation and self-defence:

    … the evidence of circumstances founding the defence is part and parcel of the incident during which the offence is committed; and it is therefore reasonable to expect the prosecution who have to prove the offence, also to disprove the existence of circumstances on which the defence might be founded.[73]

    6.104      By contrast, in many cases of duress the offence is committed during a sequence of events that is likely to be separate from those in which the threat was made. This is so even though the law requires the threat made to be in terms that, if the threat is to be averted, a criminal act must be done more or less immediately. By contrast, a provoked reaction or the need to act in self-defence is likely to immediately materialise in response to the conduct of V him or herself. Further, in cases of duress, the person making the threat, D and V are almost always different people. In cases of duress, V may well not be present or even nearby when the threat is made. The separation of the two events in duress cases (the making of the threat and the carrying out of the criminal act) is liable to create extra difficulty for the prosecution to discharge its burden. This is a difficulty over and above the problem – common to both provocation and duress – that D may be the sole source of the evidence that provides the foundation for the defence.

    6.105      Where the criminal act is part of the same sequence of events which give rise to the evidence founding the defence, as in most cases of provocation and self-defence, there may be independent evidence as to how the offence was committed that can assist the prosecution. For example, there may be evidence that the offence was committed in a highly deliberate or ruthless fashion that undermines a claim that it occurred during a loss of temper or in response to an immediate need to take evasive action. Such evidence cannot in itself undermine a claim of duress because it could be that D was only acting, as he or she claims, in exactly the same way that the person making the threat demanded that he or she should act.

    6.106      Further, as we now explain, in cases of duress, even if the relevant facts may be verified by sources other than D, those sources may be difficult to access in a way that is not realistically true in cases of provocation and self-defence.

    Duress emanating from or relating to acts outside the jurisdiction

    6.107      The dual problems of difficulty in disproving the defence and the relative ease with which it can be concocted are particularly acute in two contexts (which may overlap). First there are cases where D claims that the duress emanated from outside the jurisdiction. In fact, such cases reveal a wider problem. At common law, duress developed at a time when it was quite exceptional for the duress to emanate from abroad. That being so, it was entirely reasonable that D could not successfully plead the defence if he or she could have invoked the assistance of the state's agents to effectively protect him or her from the threat of death or serious harm. However, this means of controlling the operation of the defence starts to break down if the source of the duress is a foreign state or the agents of that state. It also comes under strain if the threat, although coming from within the jurisdiction, consists of, for example, a threat to kill D's wife and children who are resident overseas in a country in which the government is powerless to protect them. As a result, the potential scope of the duress defence is widened and it is widened in circumstances that make it very difficult for the prosecution to adduce evidence to disprove false claims.

    6.108      It is right to acknowledge, however, that in such cases D may encounter similar difficulties in obtaining evidence to support what is an authentic claim of duress. However, in the context of an evidential gap, there are two factors that might make it easier for D to discharge the burden of proof compared to the prosecution. First, if a legal burden were to be imposed on D, he or she would only be required to prove duress on the balance of probabilities. In contrast, the prosecution is required to disprove duress beyond reasonable doubt. Secondly, D is in a position to provide his or her own testimony as evidence. In contrast, the prosecution cannot compel D to provide evidence, subject to D first discharging the evidential burden required to raise duress. It would not always be necessary for D to testify in order to discharge the evidential burden, so long as the matter had been raised at interview.

    Collaboration between criminals

    6.109      The second context in which the prosecution may encounter particular difficulties in disproving duress, and where there are likely to be false claims of duress, are cases where both the person making the threat and the perpetrator of the crime are themselves loosely associated through criminal activity. In an earlier report we said that, "… members of a criminal gang might well be capable, not only individually, but in collusion, of concocting a false defence of duress."[74] The current law, of course, denies the defence of duress to gang members who make threats against one another.[75] Nevertheless, there remains a risk that D could succeed in a false claim of duress in many cases where the prosecution will be unable to prove D's voluntary membership of or association with a criminal organisation. An example would be where a former prisoner is paid by former fellow inmates to agree that he will say that he threatened them into perpetrating criminal acts.

    DISTINGUISHING MURDER AND ATTEMPTED MURDER FROM OTHER OFFENCES

    6.110      It is not within our remit to consider whether D should bear the burden of disproving duress as a defence to offences other than first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder. We are conscious that recommending that D should bear the burden of proving duress as a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, will result in different burdens depending on the offence to which duress was being pleaded as a defence.

    6.111      We acknowledge that the fact that first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder involve a uniquely serious actual or intended harm does not, in itself, justify a reverse burden of proof. We are, after all, not recommending that D should bear the burden of proving provocation. Rather, we believe that a combination of factors justifies the imposition of a reverse burden of proof. These are the difficulty of disproving duress, the relative ease with which the defence can be concocted, the uniquely serious nature of murder and attempted murder and the duties imposed by Article 2 of the European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms ("the ECHR").

    Article 2 of the ECHR

    6.112      It is important to stress that that our recommendation is that duress should be a full and not a partial defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder. Article 2 of the ECHR provides that no one shall be deprived of his or her life intentionally save in the execution of a sentence of a court following conviction of a crime for which the penalty of loss of life is provided by

    law. Article 2 requires not only that the state must refrain from taking life intentionally but also that appropriate steps are taken by the state to safeguard life. Where a defence, such as provocation, only has the effect of reducing murder to a lesser homicide offence, it may be argued that the state has taken appropriate steps to safeguard the life of V because D can be convicted of that lesser offence. Where a defence leads to a complete acquittal, it is the conditions in which the defence can be pleaded successfully that may have to be structured so as to satisfy the 'appropriate steps' requirement.

    6.113      Under our recommendations, in cases where D pleads duress as a defence to first degree murder, it would be admitted that he or she had unjustifiably killed an innocent person and that he or she had done so with the requisite fault element. The requisite fault element includes an intention to kill. If the burden were to be placed on the prosecution to disprove a claim that the killing took place excusably under duress, that explicitly countenances situations in which D must be acquitted in the following instance:

    (1) D admits unjustifiably and intentionally killing;
    (2) D is lying about the alleged duress;
    (3) the jury suspects that D is lying;
    (4) but the jury cannot be sure that D is lying.
    The obligation under Article 2 is to provide effective measures to ensure that the substance of Article 2 is secured.[76] If those charged with murder on the basis of having unjustifiably and intentionally killed can plead duress secure in the knowledge that the prosecution are unlikely to be able to disprove the defence, then it becomes questionable whether the state is effectively discharging its obligation under Article 2.[77]

    6.114      What is more, appropriate steps must be taken to safeguard life in relation to the permitted scope of all homicide offences that involve a high degree of threat to life. This means that the situation described in paragraph 6.113 must be avoided as much in cases of second degree murder and attempted murder as in cases of first degree murder.

    CONCLUSION

    6.115      Accordingly, subject to it being compatible with Article 6(2) of the ECHR, we recommend that a person charged with first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder should bear the legal burden of proving the qualifying conditions of the defence on a balance of probabilities. In doing so, we are confirming the recommendation that the Commission made in 1993.[78]

    Compatibility with Article 6(2) of the ECHR[79]

    6.116      Both the European Court of Human Rights in Strasbourg ("the Strasbourg Court") and the House of Lords have considered the question of the compatibility of reverse burdens of proof with article 6(2) ECHR. The approach of the Strasbourg Court is to consider whether the individual applicant, on the particular facts, has been the victim of a breach of article 6(2). In contrast, the House of Lords asks whether a particular legislative provision is incompatible with article 6(2). However, general principles relevant to the interpretation of article 6(2) may be drawn from the jurisprudence of both courts.

    THE STRASBOURG JURISPRUDENCE

    6.117      The leading case on article 6(2) is Salabiaku v France.[80] According to Lord Bingham,[81] the general principles which may be drawn from the Strasbourg jurisprudence are as follows:

    (1) It is open to states to define the constituent elements of a criminal offence.
    (2) The ECHR does not prohibit the operation of presumptions of fact or law as a matter of general principle.
    (3) However, article 6(2) does not regard presumptions of fact or law with indifference. Rather, "[i]t requires states to confine them within reasonable limits which take account of the importance of what is at stake and maintain the rights of the defence."[82]
    (4) The substance and effect of any presumption adverse to a defendant must be examined and found to be reasonable.
    THE HOUSE OF LORDS' CASES

    6.118      The leading House of Lords cases are R v DPP, ex parte Kebilene,[83] Lambert,[84] Johnstone[85] and DPP v Sheldrake; Attorney-General's Reference (No 4 of 2002) ("Sheldrake").[86] When considering whether a reverse legal burden is compatible with article 6(2), their Lordships have found that, in concert with the principles laid down in the Strasbourg Court, the presumption of innocence may be qualified provided that two conditions have been fulfilled. The first condition is that the reverse burden must be imposed in pursuance of a legitimate aim. The second is that it must be proportionate to the achievement of that aim.[87] Therefore, in deciding whether the reverse burden is compatible with article 6(2), the following three stage test should be applied:

    (1) Is there an interference with the right contained in article 6(2)?
    (2) Does the interference have a legitimate aim?
    (3) Is the effect of the provision proportionate to the legitimate aim?

    6.119      The domestic courts have rejected adopting a blanket rule as to how these criteria apply to reverse onuses. Instead the validity of a reverse onus is to be determined on an examination of all the facts and circumstances of the case.[88] If the reverse legal burden is found to be incompatible with article 6(2), the House of Lords will enquire whether it can 'read down' the burden to an evidential one, in accordance with section 3 of the Human Rights Act 1998.[89]

    IS THERE AN INTERFERENCE?

    6.120      On one view, there can be no interference with the presumption of innocence provided the reverse burden of proof applies only to a defence as distinct from the constituent elements of the offence itself. If nothing in the definition of the offence infringes article 6(2), then a defence that serves only to improve D's situation cannot be regarded as a violation of article 6(2). This was the position adopted by the minority in Sheldrake.[90]

    6.121      However, the majority in Sheldrake rejected the above reasoning, finding that there could be an interference with the presumption of innocence in these circumstances. The same view had been taken by the majority of their Lordships in the earlier cases of Lambert and Johnstone. In Johnstone, Lord Nicholls stated:

    … if an accused is required to prove a fact on the balance of probability to avoid conviction, this permits a conviction in spite of the fact-finding tribunal having a reasonable doubt as to the guilt of the accused…."[91]

    6.122      In light of the above authorities, a court examining a reverse burden of proof for duress in cases of first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder cases may well conclude that there was an interference with the presumption of innocence. However, we do not regard this as a foregone conclusion. In our view, the presumption of innocence is much more plausibly found to exist in relation to a fully justificatory defence than in relation to an excusatory defence. Although in some cases of duress the circumstances come close to being justifications for killing, they cannot justify intentionally killing in the way that, for example, acting necessarily and proportionately in self-defence does.

    IS THERE A LEGITIMATE AIM?

    6.123      It is likely that the House of Lords would accept that avoiding the dangers of false claims of duress in relation to the murder or attempted murder of an innocent person was a legitimate legislative aim. Such claims may be difficult to disprove. There would be a clear public interest in ensuring that those who commit first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder should not go unpunished. Further, there is a legitimate aim in ensuring that the state complies with its obligations under Article 2 of the ECHR.[92]

    IS THE INTERFERENCE PROPORTIONATE?

    6.124      Proportionality is the issue on which the reverse burden of proof cases have turned. In applying the proportionality test, the question is always one of balance between the magnitude of the problem and the magnitude of the interference. In Johnstone,[93] Lord Nicholls said:

    The more serious the punishment which may flow from conviction, the more compelling must be the reasons. The extent and nature of the factual matters required to be proved by the accused, and their importance relative to the matters required to be proved by the prosecution, have to be taken into account. So also does the extent to which the burden on the accused relates to facts which, if they exist, are readily provable by him as matters within his own knowledge or to which he has ready access.[94]
    We now consider the relevant factors that Lord Nicholls referred to.
    The seriousness of the offence and the severity of the penalty

    6.125      Undoubtedly, the courts have placed a considerable emphasis on the seriousness of the offence and the severity of the penalty. The more serious the offence for which D stands to be convicted, the more important it is that the burden of proof falls on the prosecution.

    6.126      However, the way in which the courts have approached the partial defences to murder of diminished responsibility and killing pursuant to a suicide pact demonstrates that a reverse burden of proof can be compatible with Article 6(2) of the ECHR, even though the offence in question is the most serious of all criminal offences. When it enacted the Homicide Act 1957, Parliament created two new partial defences to murder, namely diminished responsibility and killing pursuant to a suicide pact. In each case, Parliament chose to place the burden of proving the defence on D.[95] The Court of Appeal, despite the unique stigma attached to a conviction for murder and the mandatory sentence of life imprisonment, has upheld the reverse burden of proof in relation to both partial defences.[96] For suicide pacts the Court of Appeal stated that:

    … Parliament was only prepared to reduce the offence of murder to manslaughter if the survivor proved the existence of such a pact. In doing so, no doubt it had in mind the fact that in many cases the only evidence of such a pact would emanate from the survivor. As Douglas Brown J pointed out in his ruling, not only will the facts necessary to establish the defence lie within the defendant's knowledge but also the reverse legal burden provides protection for society from murder disguised as a suicide pact killing.[97]

    6.127      On one view, diminished responsibility is a special case because the defence is dependent upon the provision of expert psychiatric evidence. Such evidence cannot be obtained without the consent of D. If the prosecution had the burden of proving the defence, there would be insuperable problems if D refused to be medically examined.

    6.128      However, the same cannot be said of the other partial defence where the burden of proof is on D, namely killing pursuant to suicide pact. We believe that it is more helpful to consider what it is that unites diminished responsibility and killing pursuant to a suicide pact. In doing so, we consider the next factor highlighted by Lord Nicholls in Johnstone.

    The extent and nature of the factual matters required to be proved by the accused, and their importance relative to the matters required to be proved by the prosecution

    6.129      The feature that diminished responsibility and killing pursuant to a suicide pact share is that they are defences that come into play only if the prosecution have proved the definitional elements of murder. More importantly, if the definitional elements themselves are satisfied, they reveal conduct on the part of D that amounts to the commission of the most serious of all wrongs. It will have been proved that D intended to kill or cause serious harm. This is in stark contrast to the conduct that was made criminal by section 11(1) of the Terrorism Act 2000 which was considered by the House of Lords in Sheldrake.[98] As Lord Bingham pointed out, a person who was innocent of any blameworthy conduct could fall within the terms of section 11(1).

    6.130      In this respect, if duress was a defence to first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, it would be no different than diminished responsibility and killing pursuant to a suicide pact. The definitional elements of the offence would have been proved and, like the partial defences, duress would not negate the definitional elements of these offences.

    The extent to which the burden on the accused relates to facts which, if they exist, are readily provable by him or her as matters within his or her own knowledge or to which he or she has ready access

    6.131      If the burden of proof were on D, D would have to prove the qualifying conditions of the defence. The qualifying conditions are all matters that are within his or her own knowledge. Importantly, they are very different from the matters that D has to prove if charged with an offence under section 11(1) of the Terrorism Act 2000. Section 11(2) provides that it is a defence for D to prove that:

    (1) the organisation was not proscribed on the last (or only) occasion on which he or she became a member or began to profess to be a member; and
    (2) he or she had not taken any part in the activities of the organisation at any time while it was proscribed.

    6.132      In Sheldrake, Lord Bingham said that it might be impossible for D to prove that he or she had not taken part in any activities of the organisation while it was proscribed:

    Terrorist organisations do not generate minutes, records or documents on which [the defendant] could rely. Other members would for obvious reasons be unlikely to come forward and testify on his behalf. If the defendant's involvement had been abroad, any evidence might also be abroad and hard to adduce. While the defendant himself could assert that he had been inactive, his evidence might well be discounted as unreliable.[99]

    6.133      However, Lord Bingham's observations have to be seen in context. The offence in question criminalised conduct that was not necessarily blameworthy. Further, if the legal burden of proof was on D, it would have involved D proving two negatives. By contrast, establishing duress would not be entirely dependent on D proving a series of negatives.

    6.134      In Makuwa[100] the Court of Appeal recently considered whether the statutory defence granted by section 31 of the Immigration and Asylum Act 1999 placed a legal burden on D of proving the matters to which it referred and further, whether the resulting infringement of article 6(2) was justifiable as a proportionate way of achieving the legitimate objective of maintaining proper immigration controls by restricting the use of forged passports. It was held, relying on Embaye [101] (a case concerning section 2 of the Asylum and Immigration Act 2004) that a legal burden was proportionate as D alone is likely to have all of the relevant information:

    In almost all cases it would be very difficult, if not impossible, for the Crown to prove that the defendant's life or freedom had not been threatened in the country from which he had come; in most cases it would be difficult, if not impossible, for the Crown to prove that he had not presented himself to the authorities in the United Kingdom without delay; in many cases it would be difficult to show that he had not shown good cause for his illegal entry or presence or that he had not made a claim for asylum as soon as was reasonably practicable after his arrival in the United Kingdom. If the burden of the defendant were no more than to adduce sufficient evidence to raise an issue in relation to matters of that kind, the statutory provisions to which s.31 relates would be rendered largely ineffective in the case of all those who came to this country claiming a right to asylum here.[102]

    6.135      Some would argue that it is no easier for D who has acted in consequence of duress committed abroad to bear the burden than it is for the prosecution to do so. In connection with this point, the Court of Appeal have recently stated:

    [W]e recognise that a defendant may be traumatised and unable to produce documents or witnesses to support his factual claims, but the jury can be trusted to make allowances for those difficulties."[103]
    The question is whether the possibility that individual cases may arise in which it is as difficult for D as for the prosecution to provide evidence about duress, should affect the choice of a general rule. We have concluded that it should not. As we have already pointed out, it must be kept in mind that if the prosecution bears the burden of proof, they must disprove duress beyond reasonable doubt, whereas if D bears the burden of proving duress, it is only on the balance of probabilities.
    CONCLUSION

    6.136      We believe that imposing a legal burden on D to prove duress on a balance of probabilities would be compatible with Article 6(2) of the ECHR. As one of our consultees, a leading QC at the criminal bar, observed:

    If however a statute were enacted which placed a burden of proof on the defendant to establish on the balance of probabilities that he acted under duress, I would not expect the courts to hold that such a provision was incompatible with article 6(2) of the ECHR. It could not be described as an intrinsic part of the offence (as is indeed exemplified by the fact that it does not currently constitute a defence at all) and it is a matter on which the defendant is well placed to provide evidence.

    6.137      The American Supreme Court by a seven to two majority has recently held that the burden of proof may be placed on the accused in duress cases.[104] Justice Kennedy said:

    The claim of duress in most instances depends upon conduct that takes place before the criminal act; and, as the person who allegedly coerced the defendant is often unwilling to come forward and testify, the prosecution may be without practical means of disproving the defendant's allegations. There is good reason, then to maintain the usual rule of placing the burden of production [ie evidential burden] and persuasion together on the party raising the issue.[105]

    6.138      Even though he dissented, Justice Breyer conceded that "there is a practical argument that favours the Government's position here, namely that defendants should bear the burden of persuasion here because defendants often have superior access to the relevant proof."[106]

    6.139      We note that in French law the burden of proving any general defence, including duress, is traditionally regarded as falling on the defendant.[107]

    Burden of proof to be consistent between first degree murder and second degree murder

    6.140      As we stated at paragraph 6.90, in the further consultation that we undertook, we asked whether the burden of proof should be the same for first degree murder and second degree murder. All consultees were of the view that the burden of proof should be the same for first degree murder and second degree murder.

    6.141      We recommend that on a charge of first degree murder, second degree murder and attempted murder, the defendant should bear the legal burden of proving the qualifying conditions of the defence of duress on a balance of probabilities.

    Children and young persons

    6.142      There was not a great deal of support among consultees for a special defence or an alternative verdict to be available to children and young persons pleading duress (such as a full defence to murder). However, a number of consultees noted that youth would be a relevant factor when determining how a reasonable person might have responded to the threats.[108] Further, youth could be taken into account in sentencing.[109] One consultee also noted that the exercise of discretion on the part of the prosecuting authorities could ensure that in appropriate cases, children and young persons were not prosecuted.[110]

    6.143      On balance, we do not consider that children and young persons who plead duress should have a special defence or verdict. We agree that any leniency that should be shown to children or young persons due to their greater vulnerability to pressure can be accounted for by the test for duress itself (which includes age as a relevant characteristic) and in sentencing.

    Complicity

    6.144      Our specific recommendations on the application of the defence of duress to secondary parties to murder are contained in Part 4.[111]

Ý
Ü   Þ

Note 1    Paras 7.18 to 7.19.    [Back]

Note 2    Howe [1987] AC 417.    [Back]

Note 3    Gotts [1992] 2 AC 412.    [Back]

Note 4    In Abdul-Hussain [1999] Criminal Law Review 570, the Court of Appeal questioned whether duress is a defence to conspiracy. However, if duress can be a defence to doing something, it is difficult to see why it cannot also be a defence to agreeing to do something.    [Back]

Note 5    Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467 at [18] by Lord Bingham.    [Back]

Note 6    The courts have not always accurately reflected the distinction – Martin (Colin) [1989] 1 All ER 652.    [Back]

Note 7    Both Smith and Hogan, Criminal Law (11th ed 2005) pp 311 to 313 and Simester and Sullivan, Criminal Law Theory and Doctrine (2nd ed 2003) pp 594 to 595 discuss whether duress can be a defence to murder before considering duress of circumstances.    [Back]

Note 8    In cases of duress of circumstances, the threat may, but need not, emanate from another person. In Willer (1986) 83 Cr App R 225 D pleaded duress of circumstances to a charge of reckless driving. The manner of his driving resulted from his being confronted by what he believed would be a violent attack by a gang of youths. The defence would have been equally available had he driven in the manner he did in order to escape a herd of charging bulls.    [Back]

Note 9    (1884) 14 QBD 273. It is true that the judgment of Lord Chief Justice Coleridge refers to “necessity” rather than duress of circumstances. Nevertheless, the case, properly analysed, is one of duress of circumstances.     [Back]

Note 10    [1982] 1 WLR 294.    [Back]

Note 11    [1987] AC 417.    [Back]

Note 12    Lord Lane had doubts as to whether a threat of serious harm should suffice. On this issue, see paras 6.73 to 6.76 below.    [Back]

Note 13    [1982] 1 WLR 294, 300. The reason why Lord Lane referred to “killing” is that the prosecution conceded that duress was capable of being a defence to murder. The House of Lords in Howe [1987] AC 417 has since made it clear that duress is not a defence to murder.    [Back]

Note 14    [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 15    For the avoidance of doubt, by ’qualifying conditions’ we mean all the elements of the defence other than the requirement that a sober person of reasonable firmness might have responded in the way that that D did.    [Back]

Note 16    In Baker and Wilkins [1997] Criminal Law Review 497 it was held that the defence was not available where the threat related to psychological injury.    [Back]

Note 17    Rodger and Rose [1998] 1 Cr App R 143; Brown [2003] EWCA Crim 2637.    [Back]

Note 18    In Shayler [2001] EWCA Crim 1977, [2001] 1 WLR 2206 the Court of Appeal referred to “persons for whom the situation makes him responsible”.    [Back]

Note 19    Safi [2003] EWCA Crim 1809, [2004] 1 Cr App R 14.    [Back]

Note 20    In Safi [2003] EWCA 1809, [2004] 1 Cr App R 14 the Court of Appeal, without having to decide the point, seemed to favour dispensing with the requirement that the belief must be reasonably as well as honestly held. However, in Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467 at [23] Lord Bingham was unequivocal, “But there is no warrant for relaxing the requirement that the belief must be reasonable as well as genuine”.     [Back]

Note 21    In Abdul-Hussain [1999] Criminal Law Review 570 the Court of Appeal suggested the threat had to be “imminent” but not “immediate”. However, in Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467, at [28] Lord Bingham referred to the threat having to be one that D reasonably expects to follow “immediately or almost immediately”.     [Back]

Note 22    In Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467 at [38] Lord Bingham, in passing, said that the defence is not available if D ought to have been aware of the risk of being subjected to any compulsion by threats of violence. On this view, it is irrelevant that D was not aware of the risk.    [Back]

Note 23    [1996] 2 Cr App R 157.    [Back]

Note 24    Specifically, the Court held that a low IQ short of mental impairment is not a relevant characteristic.    [Back]

Note 25    [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 26    Above, at [21].    [Back]

Note 27    Para 7.32.    [Back]

Note 28    Paras 7.3 and 7.44.    [Back]

Note 29    Para 7.73.    [Back]

Note 30    Para 7.50.    [Back]

Note 31    It is true that an alternative basis for convicting D of first degree murder would be that he or she foresaw that it was virtually certain that V would die. However, it has to be remembered that a finding by the jury that D foresaw death as a virtual certainty entitles but does not compel the jury to find that D intentionally killed.    [Back]

Note 32    Under our recommendations, D would be liable to be convicted of first degree murder if he or she was a party to a joint venture and foresaw that another party to the joint venture might commit first degree murder – see Part 4.    [Back]

Note 33    See paras 6.36 to 6.65.    [Back]

Note 34    Treacy J, Crown Prosecution Service, the Police Federation, and the Association of Chief Police Officers.     [Back]

Note 35    Paras 6.26 to 6.27 above.    [Back]

Note 36    Contrary to Offences Against the Person Act 1861, s 18.    [Back]

Note 37    Including Elias J, the Criminal Bar Association, the Law Society, the London Criminal Courts Solicitors’ Association and Liberty. Professor David Ormerod thought that “[t]he argument that it ought to operate as a full defence has not been adequately rebutted.”     [Back]

Note 38    Report on Defences of General Application (1977) Law Com No 83, para 2.43 cited with approval by the Commission in Legislating the Criminal Code: Offences against the Person and General Principles (1993) Law Com No 218, para 30.17.    [Back]

Note 39    Paras 6.59 to 6.65 below.    [Back]

Note 40    Some who subscribe to this view would go further and maintain that it should never be even a partial defence to first degree murder.    [Back]

Note 41    Dudley and Stephens (1884) 14 QBD 273 is an example.    [Back]

Note 42    [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 43    Contrary to Infant Life (Preservation) Act 1929, s 1.    [Back]

Note 44    Contrary to Offences Against the Person Act 1861, s 58.    [Back]

Note 45    The scenarios are taken from Professor K J M Smith, A Modern Treatise of the Law of Criminal Complicity (1991) p 80.    [Back]

Note 46    Under our recommendations, death or life-threatening harm.    [Back]

Note 47    Under our recommendations, D would commit first degree murder not only if he or she intended to kill but also if D intended to cause serious harm aware that there was a serious risk of causing death. On one view, if D, under threat of death to others for whom he or she is responsible, does an act intended to cause serious harm but in the realisation that it carries a serious risk of causing death, his or her conduct can be characterised as justified. This is because D has acted in order to save innocent lives without intending to take life.    [Back]

Note 48    See our earlier report Partial Defences to Murder (2004) Law Com No 290 paras 3.28 to 3.30    [Back]

Note 49    DPP for Northern Ireland v Lynch [1975] AC 653, 671, by Lord Morris.    [Back]

Note 50    Report on Defences of General Application (1977) Law Com No 83, para 2.16.    [Back]

Note 51    See n 15 above.    [Back]

Note 52    Ms Lumsdon, Mr Samuels and Mr Taylor.    [Back]

Note 53    The Criminal Bar Association and Graham Virgo.    [Back]

Note 54    Nicola Padfield.    [Back]

Note 55    Justice.    [Back]

Note 56    A Criminal Code for England and Wales (1989) Law Com No 177, vol 2 Commentary on Draft Criminal Code Bill para 12.15; Legislating the Criminal Code: Offences against the Person and General Principles (1993) Law Com No 218, paras 29.9 to 29.10.    [Back]

Note 57    It is true that for a plea of self-defence to succeed, the degree of force employed by D must have been reasonable in the circumstances as he or she believed them to be. However, D’s belief in the need to resort to self-defence need only be an honest belief – Williams (Gladstone) [1987] 3 All ER 411.    [Back]

Note 58    Palmer v R [1971] AC 814, 832.     [Back]

Note 59    Graham [1982] 1 WLR 294; Howe [1987] AC 417; Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 60    [2000] 2 Cr App R 42.    [Back]

Note 61    [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 62    See para 6.8(2) above.    [Back]

Note 63    [1996] 2 Cr App R 157.    [Back]

Note 64    [2005] UKPC 23, [2005] 2 AC 580.    [Back]

Note 65    It is also consistent with the decision on relevant characteristics in relation to provocation in A-G for Jersey v Holley [2005] UKPC 23, [2005] 2 AC 580.    [Back]

Note 66    [1982] 1 WLR 294.    [Back]

Note 67    R (O) v Crown Court at Harrow [2006] UKHL 42, [2006] 3 WLR 195 at [11].    [Back]

Note 68    See S [2006] EWCA Crim 756, [2006] 2 Cr App R 23 where the Court of Appeal held that the decision whether or not to stay proceedings on the grounds of abuse of process involved an exercise of judicial assessment dependent upon judgement. The Court said that it was potentially misleading to apply to the exercise of that discretion the language of burden and standard of proof.    [Back]

Note 69    Woolmington v DPP [1935] AC 462.    [Back]

Note 70    The evidential burden can be discharged by prosecution evidence. Eg, the prosecution adduce evidence of what D said when interviewed by the police. In the course of the interview, D says that he or she committed the offence as a result of being confronted by potentially lethal violence.    [Back]

Note 71    [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467 at [20].    [Back]

Note 72    Legislating the Criminal Code: Offences against the Person and General Principles (1993) Law Com No 218, para 33.6.    [Back]

Note 73    Above.    [Back]

Note 74    Above, at para 33.12.    [Back]

Note 75    Z [2005] UKHL 22, [2005] 2 AC 467.    [Back]

Note 76    Z v UK (2002) 34 EHRR 3 at [73].    [Back]

Note 77    It is also true that D may kill intentionally when acting in self-defence and yet he or she bears only an evidential burden in relation to that defence, in spite of the fact that a successful plea also leads to a complete acquittal. However, cases of self-defence are different, even though there may be just as much of a risk that D is lying. The right to kill in self defence is itself protected by Article 2(2). That explains our reference to the need for an intentional killing to be unjustified if it is to raise the Article 2 point.    [Back]

Note 78    Legislating the Criminal Code: Offences against the Person and General Principles (1993) Law Com No 218, at para 33.16.    [Back]

Note 79    Article 6(2) ECHR reads: Everyone charged with a criminal offence shall be presumed innocent until proven guilty according to law.    [Back]

Note 80    (1991) 13 EHRR 379.    [Back]

Note 81    Sheldrake [2004] UKHL 43, [2005] 1 AC 264 at [12] and [21].    [Back]

Note 82    Salabiaku v France (1991) 13 EHRR 379 at [28].    [Back]

Note 83    [2000] 2 AC 326.    [Back]

Note 84    [2001] UKHL 37, [2002] 2 AC 545.    [Back]

Note 85    [2003] UKHL 28, [2003] 1 WLR 1736.    [Back]

Note 86    [2004] UKHL 43, [2005] 1 AC 264.    [Back]

Note 87    I Dennis, “Reverse Onuses and the Presumption of Innocence: in Search of Principle” (2005) Criminal Law Review 901, 902.     [Back]

Note 88    Lambert [2001] UKHL 37, [2002] 2 AC 545 at [34]; Sheldrake [2004] UKHL 43, [2005] 1 AC 264 at [21].    [Back]

Note 89    The Human Rights Act 1998, s 3, reads: (1) So far as it is possible to do so, primary legislation and subordinate legislation must be read and given effect in a way which is compatible with Convention rights.    [Back]

Note 90    Lord Rodger and Lord Carswell.    [Back]

Note 91    [2003] UKHL 28, [2003] 1 WLR 1736, 1750 by Lord Nicholls.     [Back]

Note 92    See paras 6.112 to 6.115 above.    [Back]

Note 93    [2003] UKHL 28, [2003] 1 WLR 1736.    [Back]

Note 94    Above, at [50].    [Back]

Note 95    Homicide Act 1957, s 2(2) in relation to diminished responsibility and s 4(2) in relation to killing pursuant to a suicide pact.    [Back]

Note 96    Lambert [2002] QB 1112; Attorney-General’s Reference (No 1 of 2004) [2004] EWCA Crim 1025, [2004] 1 WLR 2111.    [Back]

Note 97    [2004] EWCA Crim 1025, [2004] 1 WLR 2111 at [130] to [132]. The Court of Appeal’s judgment was subject to some adverse comment by Lord Bingham in Sheldrake [2004] UKHL 43, [2005] 1 AC 264 at [29] to [32]. However, Lord Bingham did not explicitly overrule the Court of Appeal on the issue of suicide pacts as it did not arise on the facts of Sheldrake.    [Back]

Note 98    Subject to the defence contained in s 11(2), s 11(1) makes it an offence to belong or profess to belong to a proscribed organisation.    [Back]

Note 99    [2004] UKHL 43, [2005] 1 AC 264 at [ 51].    [Back]

Note 100    [2006] EWCA Crim 175, [2006] 2 Cr App R 11.    [Back]

Note 101    [2005] EWCA Crim 2865.    [Back]

Note 102    Makuwa [2006] EWCA Crim 175, [2006] 2 Cr App R 11 at [36] by Moore-Bick LJ.    [Back]

Note 103    Embaye [2005] EWCA Crim 2865 at [29].    [Back]

Note 104    Dixon v US (2005) 413F 3rd 520.    [Back]

Note 105    Above, 2 to 3.    [Back]

Note 106    Above, 4. Justice Breyer goes on to contrast (as we have contrasted) the position in duress cases with the position in provocation cases. In provocation cases he says that proving an absence of passion in murder, “imposes no unique hardship on the prosecution”, citing Mullaney v Wilbur 421 US 702.    [Back]

Note 107    Jean Pradel, Manuel de procédure pénale, (10th ed, 2000), §380    [Back]

Note 108    The Criminal Bar Association, the Law Society, Mr Graham Virgo and Justice.    [Back]

Note 109    Wilkie J, the Crown Prosecution Service, the Society of Labour Lawyers, Mr Samuels and Nicola Padfield.    [Back]

Note 110    Society of Labour Lawyers.    [Back]

Note 111    See paras 4.37 to 4.41.    [Back]

Ý
Ü   Þ


BAILII: Copyright Policy | Disclaimers | Privacy Policy | Feedback | Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/ew/other/EWLC/2006/304(6).html