BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you
consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it
will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free
access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[New search]
[Help]
Alan Merry and Alexander McCall Smith, Errors, Medicine
and the Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2001), ISBN 0 521
00088 2, pb £17.95
Reviewed by Jane Wright
Book Review Editor
Errors, Medicine and the Law is a most timely contribution to
the enduring debate about how society should respond to accidents in general,
and medical accidents in particular. It is a work that challenges us to rethink
our approach to the evaluation of error and the role that blame plays in that
evaluation. Its central thesis is that many events that are categorised as
errors do not involve moral culpability and that litigation, far from promoting
greater safety in medicine, induces secrecy and silence that conspire to inhibit
the reduction of medical accident. This is a provocative and challenging book
that is in tune with an emerging consciousness that we must fundamentally
rethink how we deal with medical error in order to make the NHS safer for
patients. The Bristol Inquiry
Report
(1) has
recommended that the clinical negligence action, as a barrier to openness,
should be abolished and replaced with an alternative compensation system. The
government has announced that a White Paper on reforming the way clinical
negligence claims are handled will be published early in
2002.
[2]
Alan Merry is a practising cardiac anaesthetist whose research focuses on
the reduction of error, particularly in anaesthesia, and Alexander McCall Smith
is Professor of Medical Law at the University of Edinburgh. The fact that the
separate disciplines of law and medicine are so ably represented gives this text
a rich flavour and illuminates the discussion in a practical way that a lawyer
alone could not hope to do.
The authors state that the book is a “study of how mishaps occur and
how people are blamed for them. In many areas of human activity there is a
strong tendency to attribute blame for accidents which, on further
investigation, may be shown not to involve any culpable conduct”
(Introduction p.1). The authors argue that many cases that have been/might be
characterised as examples of clinical negligence do not involve moral
culpability and that a safer system of care would be promoted if we understand
better the factors that underlie the errors that cause medical harm.
Chapter 1 is described as a “chapter of accidents”(p.6). The
authors describe the various events that led up to the sinking of the Titanic
and the explosion of the space shuttle Challenger. Both are good examples of how
difficult it frequently is in the aftermath of a disaster to isolate cause. Each
incident occurred as the cumulative effect of a series of conditions. In the
case of Challenger, for example, ring seals failed that caused fuel to escape
and explode. That failure was caused by the exposure of the seals to low
temperatures on the ground. The launch was approved by a team of people who were
grossly sleep-deprived and under pressure to meet deadlines. That pressure
reflected the operational culture of NASA, with the result that the advice from
engineers was overruled by managers who were under budgetary pressure from
politicians. This catalogue of conditions led to tragedy. The authors use this
and other examples to highlight the multi-factorial nature of accidents and the
fact that the instinct of human beings is to seek someone to isolate and blame.
Unfortunately, the fact that people may appreciate that an accident is
multi-factorial is not accompanied by a change in blaming behaviour. This is the
case with medical accidents, where, as Merry and McCall Smith point out, in many
adverse events it is the system itself that is at fault: tired medical staff and
inadequate resources may contribute to medical harm, therefore should blame
necessarily be laid upon the individual doctor where a systemic failure occurs?
The authors use the example of drug error to illustrate their argument that
some types of error should be regarded as slips or lapses that are an inevitable
part of human behaviour and not culpable. They give the example of a Dr.
Yogosakaran who faced with an emergency after an operation, the surgeon and
scrub nurse having left the operating theatre, mistakenly injected the patient
with the wrong drug. It would seem that the doctor had gone to the right drawer,
but another person, who was never identified, had put the wrong drug in the
drawer. The patient suffered brain damage and died. The doctor on finding the
empty ampoule realised what he had done and reported his error to the hospital
authorities. The doctor’s honesty led to his conviction for manslaughter.
The authors argue that while this looks like a case of negligence other
factors were at work that would argue against a finding of culpability. They
argue that the patient was high risk and should not have been treated at the
relevant hospital and that the defendant was not adequately supervised so that
there was a systems failure. The authors also argue (this is developed in
Chapters 2 and 3) that the legal process should take account of human cognition
function and recognise ‘confirmation bias’ i.e. that there is a
tendency for people to read what they expect to see. Thus, a similarly named
drug in the wrong drawer might reasonably lead to a mistake being made. The
authors highlight the fact that courts and lawyers look for the ‘smoking
gun’ when determining blame and focus on isolated acts, rather than
context, a theme to which they return in subsequent chapters.
In Chapter 2,
The human factor, a number of alarming statistics are
put forward that demonstrate just how ‘highly prone’ is medical
practice to going wrong (p.43). The central argument is that error is inevitable
in any doctor’s career and that “disciplinary or legal processes
which may flow from such events need to distinguish genuinely culpable practices
from the human errors which are inevitable in any doctor’s career”
(p.45). It is at this point that this reviewer began to feel less sympathy with
the authors’ central arguments regarding error and blame. The requirements
to prove breach of duty and causation as well as the cost of litigation make it
notoriously difficult to mount a successful negligence action against members of
the medical profession. The authors state in their
Introduction that they
are writing about accidents and blame generally, but the focus of the work is on
medical accidents and this chapter seems to suggest that we should make a
special case for doctors. It is true that the personal and professional
consequences for a doctor who is subject to civil proceedings may be severe
(p.246), but why should the negligent be exculpated? This reviewer was not
convinced when reading Chapter 2 that the authors would necessarily make the
same argument for other professionals, although this must be the logical
consequence of their discussion. However, in their Conclusion they state that
“the occupation of the individual is not relevant, it is the general issue
of culpability in particular circumstances” (p.247).
In Chapter 2, the authors continue their theme that it is inappropriate to
judge
isolated events when we evaluate the behaviour of the professional.
They make the point that human beings are not machines and should not be
expected to behave as such: indeed, their very strength is that, unlike a
machine, they are able to react to events for which they have not been
specifically programmed. For example, unlike a machine, a human being can stop a
task and evacuate a building when it is on fire. Therefore, say the authors,
“it is irrational to judge human actions in isolation or by the standards
which we would apply to the functioning of a machine. An individual’s
actions should be judged in relation to the other people and technologies
involved. Such judgements also need to take account of the way in which the
human mind actually works” (p.56). The authors are arguing here that when
we determine what are appropriate standards of behaviour account should be taken
of human cognition processes. This a highly innovative argument: in clinical
negligence litigation, the focus is on what the actor actually did and evidence
is adduced of what s/he should have done, not the likely thought processes that
might reasonably lead to error. To take just one example, the issue of
‘confirmation bias’, referred to above, provides a good illustration
put forward by the authors: “The effect of this is that, having once
formulated an idea of events or of their surroundings, people have a strong
tendency to interpret other information in such a way as to confirm or
strengthen their initial interpretation of circumstances” (p.61). The
simple example of proofreading a manuscript demonstrates that the human mind
will see what it expects to see so that a missing or repeated word may easily go
unnoticed. The authors argue that viewed in such a light, a drug administration
error (such as that made by Dr. Yogosakaran) may appear far less reprehensible.
While this argument may be persuasive, it must not be forgotten that a drug
administration error may (fortunately, infrequently) lead to very serious harm
and even death, as in the example used by Merry and McCall Smith. To take into
account the vagaries of human cognitive processes looks unduly favourable to the
medical profession when compared with patient suffering. The authors argue that
the regulation of medicine is about achieving a balance between patient and
professional interests. To forgive certain errors because they are
understandable fails sufficiently to take account of the injured patient who may
require to be compensated. One way of doing this would be to remove the
possibility of suit in negligence and to replace the current tort system with a
no-fault compensation scheme. However, the authors do not explicitly argue for
this and they suggest that the standard of care should reflect cognition and
other issues, which would make a successful medical negligence action yet more
unlikely. This would surely tip the balance too far in favour of the medical
profession.
Chapters 3 and 4 contain a discussion of ‘Errors’ and
‘Violations’, respectively, with a view to demonstrating that a
proper understanding “of the processes which underlie human errors and
contribute to modern-day disasters is essential to any meaningful analysis of
blame” (p.97). The authors argue that a distinction should be drawn
between errors and violations. Errors are an inevitable by-product of complex
systems of human activity. An error is unintentional, a mistake, and inherently
less reprehensible than a violation which is a deliberately unsafe act. This
does not mean that the error is associated with an automatic action, it is not.
What happens is that there is “some intended aspect of the act or plan
which ‘goes wrong’, although the error itself is unintentional. In
such situations the doctor is doing their best to achieve a good result, but
something goes wrong. A violation on the other hand involves the “knowing
breach of an identifiable principle” (p.100).
The authors do not give a clear answer to the question of whether an error
should ever be considered morally culpable. They state that since an error does
not involve any deliberate element, perhaps the answer should be no. However,
there may be cases that manifest as if an error, but in fact occur through an
antecedent violation. The example is given of a doctor who makes an honest
mistake, perhaps by failing to carry out a diagnostic test, but where his/her
skill has been limited by poor application at medical school, which would be a
violation. Merry and McCall Smith acknowledge that it may be very difficult in
some circumstances to decide whether an event should be classified as an error
or a violation and that the answer may well hinge upon the honesty of the
individual.
Chapter 5 provides an analysis of the concepts of negligence, recklessness
and blame with a view to eliciting indicators as to when behaviour that causes
‘accident’ becomes culpable. The authors classify blame into five
levels, from level one which is pure causal blame where an actor in fact caused
an ‘accident’ but through no fault, through to level five, which
would reveal an intention to cause harm. This chapter is of particular interest
to tort lawyers in particular the discussion of level two blame where conduct is
measured “against a standard which sets out what
ought to be done
in the circumstances in question” (p.133). This is the language of
negligence, the setting of an objective standard of conduct that must be
reached. The authors point out that whether conduct is determined to be
negligent will depend on the question asked. In relation to drug error, if
“the question is: is it reasonable to give the wrong drug? The answer
to that would seem to be no. No expert could ever say that giving the wrong drug
is the appropriate thing to do, that is, the expected or standard thing to do.
The conduct is therefore, in this sense at least wrong. If, instead, the
question is:
could this have been done by a reasonably skilled and
competent practitioner? Then the answer, as we have seen in chapters 2 and 3
[where such an error might be classified as a slip or lapse, rather than a
violation, and therefore as not culpable], must be yes. In fact, the empirical
and theoretical data both lead us to believe that all practitioners make this
type of mistake at some time even when trying their best to avoid errors. ....
Thus one might go a step further and phrase the question as follows: is it
reasonable for a practitioner to make one mistake in (for example) one thousand
drug administrations? On this basis it is hard to conclude that such an act
should be construed as negligent (p.134).”
Thus, the authors are critical of the fact that in the negligence action a
person’s professionalism will be judged by reference to a single act in
what might be a lifetime of high professional standards. Even the most skilled
and conscientious practitioners make errors and it might be seen as unreasonable
to impose this standard of care given that error is an inevitable occurrence in
professional life. It is suggested by the authors that the
‘snapshot’ approach might be acceptable in a legal action that is
utilised for loss adjustment purposes only and that carries no overtone of
opprobrium. The authors therefore examine the negligence action to establish
whether the basis of liability carries a moral component. They conclude that,
formally, there are no moral overtones, but “such an action is almost
always viewed, both by public and the defendant, as an allegation of culpable
conduct. ... There is evidence of considerable impact on doctors and other
health professionals of malpractice actions” (p.140). However, the danger
is that in the concern to ensure “fairness” of treatment of the
health care professional the interests of the patient are susceptible to being
diminished. In this reviewer’s view it would be completely inappropriate
to adjust the normative standard to take account of either a
professional’s generally reasonable behaviour or the fact that the error
in question is one that a reasonable practitioner might make. Until large-scale
reform occurs a patient must use the tort system to secure compensation. While
it is unfortunate that a ‘good’ doctor’s career may be
blemished by a finding of negligence, that should not be used as an argument to
deny a patient a justified claim to compensation. A career is one thing, the
physical health of individuals quite another.
Chapter 6 examines the standard of care applied in negligence and asks
whether the
Bolam standard (
Bolam v.
Freiern Hospital
Management Committee [1957] 2 All ER 118), as modified by
Bolitho v.
City & Hackney Health Authority [1997] 4 All ER 771 is excessively
high. The authors are critical of the fact that according to
Bolitho the
court reserves to itself the power to evaluate expert opinion in order to ensure
that it is logical and defensible. In such circumstances, argue the authors, how
can a medical practitioner imagine how his conduct will be viewed by a court in
the future. A doctor can know if he is acting in accordance with received
medical opinion: it is much more difficult to second-guess a court. This is all
true, but, equally,
Bolitho represents a welcome break from the
paternalism and protectionism of
Bolam. It is interesting to note that
the authors do not apparently voice any disapproval of
Edward Wong Finance
Co. Ltd v.
Johnson, Stokes and Master [1984] AC 296, where the court
rejected the customary conveyancing practice of Hong Kong solicitors.
Chapter 7 provides an interesting examination of the role of the expert
witness in assessing the standard to be achieved when a defendant’s action
is being evaluated. The point is made that an expert is likely to be unusually
knowledgeable in the relevant area that after all is why s/he is appointed by
the court. The expert will focus on a narrow area, it will be research interest,
s/he will be completely up to date and furthermore, having prepared for a trial
will be completely on top of the detail. By comparison the doctor may well be a
general practitioner with a wide, but less detailed knowledge base, and s/he may
have been acting in a pressurised situation. Thus, the scales are not evenly
balanced.
Finally, in Chapter 8, the authors examine how the needs of the injured
might be addressed apart from the tort system. They acknowledge that if there
were no alternatives then it is arguable that the negative consequences of tort
litigation should be accepted as inevitable. The authors detail a number of
alternatives including the accident compensation scheme in New Zealand and the
no-fault compensation scheme that operates in Finland. The concept of fault was
reintroduced into the New Zealand scheme in 1992. In their Conclusion the
authors state that “If a way could be found for compensation to be paid
without any finding of negligence with all that entails in terms of blame and
moral censure, this would be highly desirable” (p.247). Undoubtedly,
publication of the government’s forthcoming White Paper is awaited with
interest.
To conclude this a highly readable, accessible text that should be read by
all those who are interested in the compensation debate, and the field of tort
law in particular.
(1)
Learning from Bristol. The Report of the Public Inquiry into
children’s heart surgery at the Bristol Royal Infirmary 1984-1995, Cm
5207, 2001.
(2)
Hansard: 4 July 2001: cols 221-222W.
BAILII:
Copyright Policy |
Disclaimers |
Privacy Policy |
Feedback |
Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/WebJCLI/2001/issue4/wright4.html