BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback] | ||
Court of Appeal in Northern Ireland Decisions |
||
You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> Court of Appeal in Northern Ireland Decisions >> Ni Chuinneagain, Re Application for Judicial Review [2022] NICA 56 (07 October 2022) URL: http://www.bailii.org/nie/cases/NICA/2022/56.html Cite as: [2022] NICA 56 |
[New search] [Printable PDF version] [Help]
Neutral Citation No: [2022] NICA 56
Judgment: approved by the court for handing down (subject to editorial corrections)* |
Ref: McC11949
ICOS No: 20/050867/01/A01
Delivered: 07/10/2022 |
IN HIS MAJESTY’S COURT OF APPEAL IN NORTHERN IRELAND
___________
ON APPEAL FROM THE HIGH COURT OF JUSTICE IN NORTHERN IRELAND
___________
IN THE MATTER OF AN APPLICATION BY CAOIMHE NI CHUINNEAGAIN FOR JUDICIAL REVIEW
___________
Before: McCloskey LJ, Horner LJ and Colton J
___________
Representation
Appellant: Mr Ronan Lavery KC and Mr Mark Bassett of counsel, instructed by Brentnall Legal
Respondent: Mr David Blundell KC and Mr Yaaser Vanderman, of counsel, instructed by the Crown Solicitor
___________
McCloskey LJ (delivering the judgment of the court)
Index
Subject Paragraph No
Introduction 1
Procedural Considerations 2
Factual Matrix 3-4
Statutory Framework 5-7
The Appellant’s Case 8-20
The Respondent's Riposte 21-30
The Issues 31
Procedural Issues 32-33
The Judicial Review Leave Test 34-44
The Article 8 ECHR Challenge 45-57
Article 8 ECHR and the Belfast and British-Irish Agreements 58-68
Article 8(2) ECHR: [1] Protection and [2] Interference 69-93
Article 8(2) ECHR: Proportionality 94-105
Our Conclusions 106-109
Introduction
Procedural Considerations
[2] This being a challenge to a first instance decision refusing leave to apply for judicial review there are certain material considerations of a procedural nature. We address these in para [32]ff infra.
Factual Matrix
“The applicant was born in Belfast and lives here. She is an Irish citizen and has an Irish passport, on which she has previously travelled abroad on a number of occasions. Her parents are also Irish citizens and she has a number of relatives who live in the Republic of Ireland, as well as in the border area. She lives in Belfast and attends an Irish-medium school. She has described in her affidavit evidence that she has a keen interest in Gaelic and Irish culture, and believes that she is “fully immersed in all aspects of Irish national culture.” Irish is her first language and she is a player of traditional Irish music.
The applicant also avers that she has never presented herself as a British citizen in any context or for any reason and says that she would not do so. She objects to the notion of ‘British citizen or subject’ being applied to her.
Although the applicant accepts that it is open to her (particularly now that she has attained the age of 18) to renounce her British citizenship, she has averred that she does not wish to do so as she considers that doing so would represent an acceptance that she was born a British citizen, in addition to having to pay the administrative cost involved.”
In addition to the foregoing, the appellant deposes that she has possessed an Irish passport, for some unspecified period, which she has invariably utilised for the purpose of external travel. She avers that she has “zero affinity with British identity.”
Statutory Framework
[5] The relevant provisions of the British Nationality Act 1981 (the “1981 Act”) are these:
Sections 1 and 2:
“1.— Acquisition by birth or adoption.
(1) A person born in the United Kingdom after commencement, or in a qualifying territory on or after the appointed day, shall be a British citizen if at the time of the birth his father or mother is—
(a) a British citizen; or
(b) settled in the United Kingdom or that territory.
…
2.— Acquisition by descent.
(1) A person born outside the United Kingdom and the qualifying territories after commencement shall be a British citizen if at the time of the birth his father or mother—
(a) is a British citizen otherwise than by descent;
…”
Section 3 of the 1981 Act sets out the circumstances in which a minor may apply for and be registered as a British citizen. Section 6 of the 1981 Act provides for persons of full age and capacity to apply for naturalisation as a British citizen if certain requirements are met. Section 11 of the 1981 Act applies to those born before 1 January 1983. It prescribes the circumstances in which citizens of the UK and Colonies would become British citizens once the 1981 Act came into force.
Section 12(1) - (4):
“12.— Renunciation
(1) If any British citizen of full age [1] and capacity makes in the prescribed manner a declaration of renunciation of British citizenship, then, subject to subsections (3) and (4), the Secretary of State shall cause the declaration to be registered.
(2) On the registration of a declaration made in pursuance of this section the person who made it shall cease to be a British citizen.
(3) A declaration made by a person in pursuance of this section shall not be registered unless the Secretary of State is satisfied that the person who made it will after the registration have or acquire some citizenship or nationality other than British citizenship; and if that person does not have any such citizenship or nationality on the date of registration and does not acquire some such citizenship or nationality within six months from that date, he shall be, and be deemed to have remained, a British citizen notwithstanding the registration.
…
(5) For the purposes of this section any person who has been married, or has formed a civil partnership, shall be deemed to be of full age.
[6] The 1981 Act repealed the British Nationality Act 1948, which defined British nationality by creating the status of "Citizen of the United Kingdom and Colonies" as the sole national citizenship of the United Kingdom and all of its colonies. The Act, which came into effect on 1 January 1949, was passed in the wake of the 1947 Commonwealth conference on nationality and citizenship, which had agreed that each of the Commonwealth member states would legislate for its own citizenship, distinct from the shared status of "Commonwealth citizen" (formerly "British subject"). This new definition of British citizenship placed Britain's colonial subjects on an equal footing with those living in the British Isles. Its ideological purpose was driven inter alia by the spectre of decolonisation. Similar legislation was also enacted in most of the other Commonwealth countries.
The Appellant’s Case
“(a) The impugned provisions are contrary to her right of effective enjoyment of citizenship of the EU, which she enjoys by virtue of her status as an Irish citizen (‘ground 1’). The applicant contends that this is contrary to articles 12 and 13 of the agreement concluded between the United Kingdom (UK) and the European Union (EU) in relation to the UK’s withdrawal from the EU in accordance with Article 50 of the Treaty of the European Union (‘the Withdrawal Agreement’).
(b) The impugned provisions are contrary to the UK’s obligations under Article 1(3) of the Ireland/Northern Ireland Protocol to the Withdrawal Agreement (‘the NI Protocol’), in particular the UK’s undertaking to protect the Belfast Agreement (also known as the Good Friday Agreement) in all its dimensions (‘ground 2’). A key feature of this aspect of the applicant’s argument is that the Belfast Agreement has now been rendered justiciable, in a way which it was not previously, by a combination of the NI Protocol and the European Union (Withdrawal) Act 2018, as amended, which implements the Withdrawal Agreement in domestic law through section 7A.
(c) The impugned provisions are contrary to the UK’s obligations under Article 2(1) of the NI Protocol, that is to say that there should be no diminution of rights, safeguards or equality of opportunity resulting from the UK’s withdrawal from the EU (‘ground 3’).
(d) The impugned provisions are contrary to her right to respect for her private life under Article 8 ECHR (‘ground 4’).
(e) The impugned provisions represent unlawful discrimination in violation of Article 14 ECHR (taken together with Article 8), in that they treat Irish citizens born in the jurisdiction of Northern Ireland in a less favourable manner than British citizens born there or Irish citizens born elsewhere but now resident in Northern Ireland (by requiring them to renounce a citizenship of which they do not wish to avail) (‘ground 5’).”
“Right to respect for private and family life
1. Everyone has the right to respect for his private and family life, his home and his correspondence.
2. There shall be no interference by a public authority with the exercise of this right except such as is in accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.”
The appellant’s case invokes only the private life dimension of article 8. The primary relief pursued by the appellant is a declaration of incompatibility under section 4 of the HRA 1998. The precise formulation is: a declaration that section 1(1) and section 12 of the British Nationality Act 1981 are incompatible with the appellant’s right to respect for private life under article 8 ECHR.
(i) Article 8 ECHR confers upon her a right to respect for her status as an Irish citizen only.
(ii) By the automatic conferral of British citizenship on the appellant at birth, section 1(1) of the 1981 Act has interfered with her right to respect for private life in a disproportionate way, contrary to article 8.
(iii) Section 12 of the 1981 Act interferes with the appellant’s right to respect for private life, contrary to article 8, by requiring her [a] to recognise and accept the status of British nationality to which she objects and [b] to pay a fee of £371 to renounce her British citizenship.
“(1) States Parties undertake to respect the right of the child to preserve his or her identity, including nationality, name and family relations as recognised by law without unlawfully interference.
(2) Where a child is illegally deprived of some or all of the elements of his or her identity, States Parties shall provide appropriate assistance and protection, with a view to re-establishing speedily his or her identity.”
“…. recognise the birth right of all the people of Northern Ireland to identify themselves and be accepted as Irish or British, or both, as they may so choose and accordingly confirm that their right to hold both British and Irish citizenship is accepted by both Governments and would not be affected by any future change in the status of Northern Ireland.”
This provision provides the basis for the following submission: it is concerned with citizenship, rather than identity; it makes no mention of Northern Irish identity; it establishes three citizenship possibilities; and it expresses these in terms of equal stature.
[16] The recitals in the British-Irish Agreement are in these terms:
“The British and Irish Governments:
Welcoming the strong commitment to the Agreement reached on 10 April 1998 by themselves and other participants in the multi-party talks and set out in Annex 1 to this Agreement (hereinafter ‘the Multi-Party Agreement’);
Considering that the Multi-Party Agreement offers an opportunity for a new beginning in relationships within Northern Ireland, within the island of Ireland and between the peoples of these islands;
Wishing to develop still further the unique relationship between their peoples and the close co-operation between their countries as friendly neighbours and as partners in the European Union;
Reaffirming their total commitment to the principles of democracy and non-violence which have been fundamental to the multi-party talks;
Reaffirming their commitment to the principles of partnership, equality and mutual respect and to the protection of civil, political, social, economic and cultural rights in their respective jurisdictions.”
Article 2 of the British-Irish Agreement on which the Appellant also relies provides:
“The two Governments affirm their solemn commitment to support, and where appropriate implement, the provisions of the Multi-Party Agreement. In particular there shall be established in accordance with the provisions of the Multi‑Party Agreement immediately on the entry into force of this Agreement, the following institutions:
(i) a North/South Ministerial Council;
(ii) the implementation bodies referred to in paragraph 9(ii) of the section entitled ‘Strand Two’ of the Multi-Party Agreement;
(iii) a British-Irish Council;
(iv) a British-Irish Intergovernmental Conference.”
[17] Being international agreements the appellant argues that both must be construed in accordance with certain principles and provisions of public international law: pacta sunt servanda, ut res magis valeat quam pereat; Articles 26–27 and 31 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties; the advisory opinion of the International Court of Justice in Admission of a State to the United Nations (1950, page 4); recognised international law texts; and the decision of the United Kingdom Supreme Court in Al-Waheed v Ministry of Defence [2017] 2 WLR 327, paras 322–326. Finally, on this issue, the appellant invokes Article 1 of the Hague Convention on the Conflict of Nationality Laws (1930):
“It is for each State to determine under its own law who are its nationals. This law shall be recognised by other States insofar as it is consistent with international conventions, international custom and the principles of law generally recognised with regard to nationality.”
The Respondent’s Riposte
(1) The appellant’s case at first instance did not include the contention that her article 8 ECHR case is bolstered by the 1998 international agreements: this is a novel case;
(2) In any event, the appellant’s construction of the two international agreements is erroneous; and
(3) Alternatively, if this is wrong, it makes no difference to the article 8 ECHR analysis.
[23] Developing the second element of their riposte, Mr Blundell and Mr Vanderman draw attention to the formulation of principle of Lord Sumption in AL‑Malki v Reyes [2019] AC 735 at para [11]:
“11. The primary rule of interpretation is laid down in article 31(1) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (1969):
‘A treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.’
The principle of construction according to the ordinary meaning of terms is mandatory (“shall”), but that is not to say that a treaty is to be interpreted in a spirit of pedantic literalism. The language must, as the rule itself insists, be read in its context and in the light of its object and purpose. However, the function of context and purpose in the process of interpretation is to enable the instrument to be read as the parties would have read it. It is not an alternative to the text as a source for determining the parties’ intentions.”
Mr Blundell and Mr Vanderman submit that there is no error in the judge’s approach, which is found at paras [21]–[22] of his judgment:
[21] There are significant issues with both aspects of this argument. First, the Agreement ‘recognises’ the birthright of the people of Northern Ireland to “identify themselves and be accepted” as British, as Irish, or both. I accept that, as a matter of international law, this recognises a right to identify oneself and be accepted as Irish only; and, relatedly, that it entails a right to be accepted by each Government which was a party to the agreement (including the UK Government) as British or Irish only. How precisely this right is to be given effect, however, is another matter. It plainly requires a choice (which is apparent from the words “as they may so choose”) but does not specify how or when that choice should be made.
[22] In addition, it seems to me unlikely that this commitment, even as a matter of international law, entailed any obligation on the Government of the United Kingdom to amend domestic provisions in relation to citizenship. That is because this particular portion of the Belfast Agreement does not purport to require new legislation (as several other parts of the Agreement expressly do), nor to confer any new rights. Rather, it is a ‘recognition’ of a pre‑existing ‘birthright.’ In short, it is an express political acceptance that people in Northern Ireland are entitled to view themselves as British only, as Irish only, or as both, and that each choice is entirely legitimate. Insofar as this portion of the Belfast or British-Irish Agreements refers to citizenship provisions, however, it merely ‘confirms’ that there is a right to hold both British and Irish citizenship (which would remain unaffected in the event of future change in the status of Northern Ireland). Had the provision been intended to require any change to the UK’s domestic legislation on citizenship one would have expected that to have been spelt out and to have been the subject of a clear obligation. This analysis is also entirely consistent with that of the Upper Tribunal (Immigration and Asylum Chamber) in De Souza (Good Friday Agreement: nationality) [2019] UKUT 355 (IAC) (‘the De Souza case’) at paragraph [39].”
[24] Next it is submitted that the judge’s approach harmonises with that of the Upper Tribunal (Immigration and Asylum Chamber) in De Souza v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2019] UKUT 355, where it was held that the Belfast Agreement did not amend the 1981 Act. There the Upper Tribunal stated at paras [36]–[40]:
“Even assuming that this amendment would apply only to those born in Northern Ireland, it would represent a radical departure from the existing law of British nationality. To make citizenship by birth in the United Kingdom (or any part of it) dependent on consent raises a host of difficult issues.
Amongst these is the point in time at which consent would be required. It cannot rationally be contended that an infant, for example, would be expected to give consent. But, even if it were assumed that consent becomes a prerequisite only once a person had achieved the age of majority, there remain questions as to whether, and, if so, how, such a person would be expected to signify consent. A person’s nationality cannot depend in law on an undisclosed state of mind, which could change from time to time, depending on how he or she felt.
These examples of the problems inherent in a system of nationality based on consent make it plain that the omission from the 1998 Act of anything touching upon the issues of self-identification and nationality was entirely deliberate on the part of the United Kingdom Parliament. The omission cannot be explained on the basis that there was no need to amend the BNA because it could be construed compatibly with Article 1(iv)/(vi), without Parliament having to spell out the necessary amendments.
The omission also underscores the correctness of the Secretary of State’s submission that, properly construed, Article 1(iv)/(vi) does not, in fact, involve giving the concept of self-identification the meaning for which the claimant argues. If the parties to the multi-party agreement and the governments of Ireland and the United Kingdom had intended the concept of self-identification necessarily to include a person’s ability to reject his or her Irish or British citizenship, it is inconceivable that the provisions would not have dealt with this expressly. By the same token, it is equally inconceivable that the far‑reaching consequences for British nationality law would not have been addressed by the 1998 Act.
Before leaving this particular issue, we agree with the written submissions of Mr McGleenan KC and Mr Henry that, if Article 1(iv)/(vi) needs to be construed as preventing the United Kingdom from conferring British citizenship on a person born in Northern Ireland, at the point of birth, the inescapable logic is that Ireland cannot confer Irish citizenship on such a person at that point either. The result is that a person born in Northern Ireland is born stateless. That would be a breach of both countries’ international obligations to prevent statelessness. It is not conceivable that the two governments intended such a result.”
“No evidence has been presented … of any material prejudice or practical instance of detriment which has arisen for this applicant by virtue of her current British citizenship …. these seem to be minimal, with the real life impacts of the applicant having British citizenship being negligible. She is effectively free to ignore it.”
Next, the judge noted the appellant’s acceptance that many will consider the automatic conferral of British citizenship a benefit rather than a detriment. Third, the judge drew attention to the appellant’s ability to renounce her British citizenship (under section 12 of the 1981 Act) having attained her majority. Fourth, he reasoned that section 1(1) performs the important function of avoiding statelessness.
The Issues
(i) Whether the test applied by the judge in refusing leave to apply for judicial review was erroneous.
(ii) Whether section 1(1) of the 1981 Act is incompatible with the appellant’s rights under article 8 ECHR.
(iii) Whether section 12 of the 1981 Act is incompatible with the appellant’s rights under article 8 ECHR.
The respondent accepted this formulation. The appellant ultimately demurred from the formulation of issue (i): see para [44] infra. There was no quibble with the terms of issues (ii) and (iii). The appellant suggested that the following issue also arises:
“As a matter of international law, is the UK in breach of its obligations under Article 1(vi) of the British-Irish Agreement by maintaining sections 1 and 12 of the 1981 Act?”
Procedural Issues
(a) If we conclude that the judge correctly decided that leave to apply for judicial review should be refused, the appeal will be dismissed and his decision affirmed.
(b) Alternatively, it would be open to this court to conclude that leave to apply for judicial review should be granted without more. This would entail allowing the appeal to this extent, reversing the decision of the judge and remitting the case to proceed to a substantive hearing at first instance.
(c) The third alternative would be to grant leave to apply for judicial review under Order 53, Rule 3, then determining the application substantively under rule 5(8) by dismissing it.
(d) The fourth, and final, alternative would be to grant leave to apply for judicial review under Order 53, rule 3 of the Rules of the Court of Judicature (NI) 1980 (“the 1980 Rules”) and then determine the application substantively under rule 5(8) in the appellant’s favour. In this event it would be necessary for the court to further decide, in the exercise of its discretion, whether any remedy should be awarded and, if so, what.
This is illustrated by the decisions of this court in Re Bignell [1997] NI 36 and Re Farrell [2009] NICA 35 para [32]. The key to the third and fourth options being available is that the procedural course adopted by the appellant in the wake of the decision at first instance has been not to renew her application for leave to apply for judicial review to this court under Order 59, rule 14(3) of the 1980 Rules, rather to appeal. The practice of this court in recent years highlights the desirability of appealing, rather than renewing. In particular, the mechanism of simply appealing will frequently have the virtues of saving costs and reducing delay.
The Judicial Review Leave Test
[35] In Re Omagh District Council’s Application [2004] NICA 10 this court stated at para [5]:
“… the court will refuse permission to claim judicial review unless satisfied that there is an arguable ground for judicial review on which there is a realistic prospect of success (see Fordham's Judicial Review Handbook, 3rd Edition, at paragraph 21.26).”
See also para [43]. In Re Donaldson’s Application [2009] 25 this court formulated the test in the following way, at para [32]:
“The test to be applied in an application for leave to bring judicial review proceedings is whether there is an arguable case having a realistic prospect of success and one which is not subject to a discretionary bar such as delay or an alternative remedy …”
[36] These formulations of the test chime with the decision of the Privy Council in Sharma v Antoine [2007] 1 WLR 780, where it was described as the “ordinary rule.” To the same effect is Maharaj v Petroleum Company of Trinidad and Tobago [2019] UKPC 21 at para [3]. We consider that there is no inconsistency between this formulation of the test and the statement of the Privy Council in Matalulu v Director of Public Prosecutions [2003] 4 LRC 712 (PC) that leave to apply for judicial review should be refused where the case appears to be “manifestly untenable.” Any case which is untenable, whether manifestly or less obviously so, cannot be considered either arguable or arguable having a reasonable prospect of success.
[37] In refusing leave to apply for judicial review the judge stated at para [30]:
“I am prepared to accept that it is arguable that the conferral of citizenship against their wishes upon a person who enjoys citizenship of another State may be an interference with their rights under Article 8 ECHR. I do so because it is arguable that citizenship can have an important impact upon a person’s social identity … [and this] … is more likely to give rise to an interference since (as a matter of law) a status is assigned to them against their wishes …
However, I cannot accept that there is any realistic prospect of the applicant succeeding on this ground when it is properly analysed.”
Founding on these passages it is submitted on behalf of the appellant that the judge applied an erroneous test. This is formulated as a freestanding ground of appeal.
“For my part, I consider that this somewhat enhanced test - rather than a threshold of simple arguability - is likely to be appropriate in many cases in this jurisdiction …. [and] … am satisfied that the present case is an appropriate case in which the enhanced threshold ought to apply …”
The judge’s assessment was that the decisions in Re Omagh DC and Sharma – see para [36]–[37] above - espoused what he described as “this somewhat enhanced test.”
[40] This court considers the correct analysis to be the following. By virtue of practice arrangements and developments there has been some detectible evolution, in both this jurisdiction and that of England and Wales, in the test to be applied in determining whether leave (permission) to apply for judicial review should be granted. In IRC v National Federation of Self Employed and Small Businesses Limited [1982] AC 617 Lord Diplock stated at 643h - 644b:
“The whole purpose of requiring that leave should first be obtained to make the application for judicial review would be defeated if the court were to go into the matter in any depth at that stage. If, on a quick perusal of the material then available, the court thinks that it discloses what might on further consideration turn out to be an arguable case in favour of granting to the applicant the relief claimed, it ought in the exercise of a judicial discretion to give him leave to apply for that relief. The discretion that the court is exercising at this stage is not the same as that which it is called upon to exercise when all the evidence is in and the matter has been fully argued at the hearing of the application.”
This formulation of the test belongs to the era in which it was pronounced. It is a reflection of the ex parte practice then prevailing and the absence of any input from the proposed respondent in terms of evidence or argument, either substantial or at all. It was also a reflection of the then more dominant principle of expedition, namely that the judicial review process was designed to provide swift resolution. Other authoritative formulations of the applicable test comparable to that of Lord Diplock can be readily found.
The Article 8 ECHR Challenge
(i) Is the right which the appellant asserts protected by article 8(1) ECHR? If “no”, the article 8 ECHR analysis ends.
(ii) If “yes”, the next question is whether section 1 and/or section 12 of the 1981 Act interfere/interferes with the appellant’s enjoyment of this right. If the answer to this question is “no”, the article 8 ECHR analysis ends.
(iii) If the answer to the first and second questions is “yes” a further question arises, namely whether the interference, in the language of article 8(2) ECHR, is in accordance with the law, pursues a legitimate aim and is necessary in a democratic society.
“(i) The concept of “private life” in Convention jurisprudence is a broad term not susceptible to exhaustive definition - Pretty v UK (2002) 35 EHRR 1, para 61.
(ii) Article 8 secures to individuals a sphere within which they can freely pursue the development and fulfilment of their personality - A.- M.V. v. Finland (2017) ECHR 273, para 76
(iii) Article 8 ECHR concerns rights of central importance to the individual’s identity, self-determination, physical and moral integrity, maintenance of relationships with others and a settled and secure place in the community. It protects a right to personal development and autonomy. This right can include a positive obligation on the state to afford official recognition of:
- a person’s gender identity as occurred in Hamalainen v Finland (2014) 1 FCR 379, para 67-68; Christine Goodwin v UK (2002) 35 EHRR 77-79;
- ethnic identity as occurred in Ciubotaru v Moldova (2010) 4 WLUK 411; Tasev v North Macedonia (2019) ECHR 346, para 32-33
- marital status as occurred in Dadouch v Malta (2014) 59 EHRR 34, para 47-50
- parental status as occurred in Rasmussen v Denmark App 8777/79 of 28 November 1984; Kruskovic v Croatia App 4618/08 of 21 June 2011, para 20; Ahrens v Germany (2012) 2 FLR 483, para 60
- Individuals must be able to establish details of their identity should as the legal parent-child relationship in Mennesson v France (2014) ECHR 664, para 96
- Right to discover one’s origins in Gaskin v UK (1990) 12 EHRR 36
(iv) This reasoning extends to citizenship. The right to citizenship comes within scope of article 8 ECHR as it amounts to an element of a person’s identity. The Strasbourg court has recognised the issue as coming within scope in, at least, the instances listed below. There is, therefore, a clear and consistent line of authority on this point:
- Genovese v Malta (2014) 58 EHRR 25, para 30
- Karassev v Finland (1999) ECHR 200
- Slivenko v Latvia (2003) ECHR 498
- Ramadan v Malta (2017) 65 EHRR 32, para 85
- K2 v United Kingdom (2019) 64 EHRR SE 18, para 49
- Usmanov v Russia (2020) ECHR 923, para 53
- Ghoumid & others v France App App 52273/16, para 43-44
- Ahmadov v Azerbaijan (2020) ECHR 96, para 42-44
- Hoti v Croatia (2018) ECHR 373, para 119–124”
[49] Article 8 ECHR has been variously described as elusive and amorphous. It is, as Stanley Burnton J memorably remarked, "the least defined and most unruly" of the Convention rights in R (Wright) v Secretary of State for Health >[2006] EWHC 2886 (Admin); >[2007] 1 All ER 825 (para [60]). In R (on the application of Countryside Alliance and others and others v Her Majesty's Attorney General and another [2007] UKHL 52 at paras [91] - [94], Lord Rodger provided a valuable resume of the jurisprudential evolution of Article 8 ECHR:
“Undoubtedly, the early decisions of the European Court on "private life" in article 8(1) tended to concern sexual and emotional relationships within an intimate circle - for which people want privacy. Article 8(1) guarantees a prima facie right to such privacy. If someone complains of a violation of that right, the essential touchstone may well be whether the person in question had a reasonable expectation of privacy: Campbell v MGN Ltd [2004] 2 AC 457, 466, para 21, per Lord Nicholls of Birkenhead.
But the European Human Rights Commission long ago rejected any Anglo-Saxon notion that the right to respect for private life was to be equated with the right to privacy. In X v Iceland (1976) 5 DR 86 the applicant complained that a law prohibiting the keeping of dogs in Reykjavik violated his article 8(1) rights. The European Court held that the right to respect for private life did not end at a right to privacy, but comprised also, to a certain degree, the right to establish and develop relationships with other human beings, especially in the emotional field, for the development and fulfilment of one's own personality. Sadly, it did not extend to developing relationships with dogs and so the Commission rejected his application as inadmissible.
It soon became clear that article 8 was not concerned merely to protect relationships in a narrow domestic field. In Niemietz v Germany (1992) 16 EHRR 97, 111, para 29, the Court held:
‘it would be too restrictive to limit the notion to an 'inner circle' in which the individual may live his own personal life as he chooses and to exclude therefrom entirely the outside world not encompassed within that circle. Respect for private life must also comprise to a certain degree the right to establish and develop relationships with other human beings.’
So article 8(1) had been violated by a search of the office where the applicant pursued his profession as a lawyer, since "it is, after all, in the course of their working lives that the majority of people have a significant, if not the greatest, opportunity of developing relationships with the outside world.”
In Pretty v United Kingdom (2002) 35 EHRR 1, 35, para 61, the European Court pointed out that "private life" in article 8(1) is "a broad term." The court also said that the notion of "personal autonomy" is an important principle underlying the interpretation of the various guarantees, including the right to "personal development", in that aspect of article 8(1).”
Moving closer to the territory of the present appeal lord Roger added at para [95]:
“In R (Razgar) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2004] 2 AC 368, 383, para 9, commenting on the reference in Pretty to the right to ‘personal development’ and to establish relationships, my noble and learned friend, Lord Bingham of Cornhill, spoke of "private life" in article 8 ‘extending to those features which are integral to a person's identity or ability to function socially as a person.’”
At para [98] Lord Roger employed the language of “features which are integral to a person's identity, of ways in which people give expression to their individuality …”
[50] What enlightenment is to be found in the Strasbourg jurisprudence? To the forefront of the appellant’s case belong the following three cases. First, in Ramadan v Malta [2017] 65 EHRR 32 the applicant, an Egyptian national by birth who later acquired Maltese citizenship, was the subject of an order depriving him of his Maltese citizenship on the basis that he had obtained this by fraud. He complained that this interfered with his right to private and family life under article 8 ECHR. At para [84] the ECtHR said the following of the evolution in its approach to loss of citizenship cases:
“ The court observes that old cases concerning loss of citizenship, whether already acquired or born into, were consistently rejected by the Convention organs as incompatible ratione materiae with the provisions of the Convention, in the absence of such a right being guaranteed by the Convention (see, for example, X v Austria , no. 5212/71 , Commission decision of 5 October 1972, Collection of Decisions 43, p.69). However, as noted above, in recent years the court has held that although the right to citizenship is not as such guaranteed by the Convention or its Protocols, it cannot be ruled out that an arbitrary denial of citizenship might in certain circumstances raise an issue under Article 8 of the Convention because of the impact of such a denial on the private life of the individual (see references mentioned at paragraph 62 above).”
It continued, at para [85]:
“ 85. Indeed, most of the cases concerning citizenship brought before the court since the above-mentioned development in the case-law have concerned applicants claiming the right to acquire citizenship and the denial of recognition of such citizenship (see, for example, Karassev , cited above), as opposed to a loss of citizenship already acquired or born into. Nevertheless, the court considers that the loss of citizenship already acquired or born into can have the same (and possibly a bigger) impact on a person’s private and family life. It follows that there is no reason to distinguish between the two situations and the same test should therefore apply. Thus, an arbitrary revocation of citizenship might in certain circumstances raise an issue under Article 8 of the Convention because of its impact on the private life of the individual. Therefore, in the present case it is necessary to examine whether the decisions of the Maltese authorities disclose such arbitrariness and have such consequences as might raise issues under Article 8 of the Convention.”
The appellant places particular reliance on this latter passage.
[51] In Hoti v Croatia [2018] ECHR 373 the applicant, who had been born in Kosovo and had been living and working in Croatia for some 13 years, from the age of 17, had his application for Croatian citizenship refused on the ground that he was unable to satisfy the statutory citizenship requirement of having a registered residence in Croatia for an uninterrupted period of five years. The applicant subsequently made an application for a permanent residence permit which was also refused on the ground that he did not satisfy the relevant statutory requirements. Although he was later granted temporary residence on humanitarian grounds for a period of some two years a decision was made refusing to extend this. This was followed by two separate extensions each of one year’s duration. All of this unfolded in what the court described as “a complex and very specific factual and legal situation related to the regularisation of the status of aliens residing in Croatia following the breakup of the former [Yugoslavia]”, at para [109]. The complaint formulated by the applicant was that he had been unlawfully erased from the register of residence in Croatia making it impossible for him to regularise his residence status, thereby rendering him stateless and interfering with his right to respect for private life under article 8 ECHR. The ECtHR determined that its adjudication would be based upon the following:
“… its case law related to the complaints of aliens who, irrespective of many years of actual residence in a host country, were not able to regularise their residence status and/or their regularisation of the residence status was unjustifiably protracted … [in breach of the State’s] … positive obligation under Article 8 of the Convention to ensure an effective enjoyment of an applicant’s private and/or family life ….”
See para [118].
“[119] At the outset, the Court reiterates that Article 8 protects, inter alia , the right to establish and develop relationships with other human beings and the outside world and can sometimes embrace aspects of an individual’s social identity. Thus, the totality of social ties between a migrant and the community in which he or she lives constitutes part of the concept of private life under Article 8 (see, mutatis mutandis , Maslov v. Austria [GC], no. 1638/03 , § 63, ECHR 2008, and Abuhmaid , cited above, § 102).
[123] … (see Abuhmaid, noted above, para 118).”
By this route the court formulated the principal question to be determined, at para [124]:
“Accordingly, in view of the nature of the applicant’s complaint and the fact that it is primarily for the domestic authorities to ensure compliance with the relevant Convention obligation, the court considers that the principal question to be examined in the present case is whether, having regard to the circumstances as a whole, the Croatian authorities, pursuant to Article 8, provided an effective and accessible procedure or a combination of procedures enabling the applicant to have the issues of his further stay and status in Croatia determined with due regard to his private-life interests (see, mutatis mutandis , Kurić and Others , cited above, §§ 357-59; Jeunesse , cited above, § 105, and Abuhmaid , cited above, § 119 )..”
The court concluded that the respondent state had not complied with its positive obligation to provide “an effective and accessible procedure or a combination of procedures enabling the applicant to have the issues of his further stay and status in Croatia determined with due regard to his private life interests under Article 8 …”
See para [141].
“ In the case of Ramadan v Malta , (no. 76136/12 , § 84, 21 June 2016) the court held that although the right to citizenship is not as such guaranteed by the Convention or its Protocols, it cannot be ruled out that an arbitrary denial of citizenship might in certain circumstances raise an issue under Article 8 of the Convention because of the impact of such a denial on the private life of the individual. To establish whether “an issue” arose under Article 8 of the Convention the court assessed whether the revocation of the citizenship was “arbitrary” and the “consequences” of revocation for the applicant (see §§ 85, 90 and 91 ibid). In the case of K2 v. the United Kingdom ((dec.), no. 42387/13 , §§ 52-64 7 February 2017), which followed, the court accepted that the revocation of citizenship amounted to an interference and applied the two-steps test to determine whether there has been a breach of Article 8 of the Convention. Subsequently, in the case of Alpeyeva and Dzhalagoniya (cited above, §§ 110‑27) the court firstly applied the “consequences” criteria to determine if there had been an interference with the applicant’s rights and then used the “arbitrariness” test to determine if there had been a breach of Article 8 of the Convention. That approach was confirmed in the case of Ahmadov v Azerbaijan (no.32538/10 , §§ 46-55, 30 January 2020). In the case of Ghoumid and Others v. France (no. 52273/16 and 4 others, §§ 43-44, 25 June 2020) the court held that nationality is an element of a person’s identity. To establish whether there had been a violation of Article 8 of the Convention the court examined as to whether the revocation of the applicant’s nationality had been arbitrary. Then, it assessed the consequences of that measure for the applicant.
In determining arbitrariness, the court should examine whether the impugned measure was in accordance with the law; whether it was accompanied by the necessary procedural safeguards, including whether the person deprived of citizenship was allowed the opportunity to challenge the decision before courts affording the relevant guarantees; and whether the authorities acted diligently and swiftly (see Ramadan, cited above, §§86‑89; K2 , cited above, §50; Alpeyeva and Dzhalagoniya , cited above, §109; and Ahmadov , cited above, § 44).
The court also reiterates that the States are entitled to control the entry and residence of aliens on their territories (see among many other authorities, Abdulaziz, Cabales and Balkandali v the United Kingdom , §67, 28 May 1985, Series A no.94, and Boujlifa v France , 21 October 1997, §42, Reports of Judgments and Decisions 1997-VI). The Convention does not guarantee the right of an alien to enter or to reside in a particular country and, in pursuance of their task of maintaining public order, Contracting States have the power to expel, for example, an alien convicted of criminal offences. However, their decisions in this field must, in so far as they may interfere with a right protected under paragraph 1 of Article 8, be in accordance with the law, pursue the legitimate aim and be necessary in a democratic society (see Slivenko v Latvia [GC], no.48321/99 , §113, ECHR 2003-X; Üner v the Netherlands [GC], no.46410/99 , §54, ECHR 2006‑XII; De Souza Ribeiro v France [GC], no.22689/07 , § 77, ECHR 2012; Mehemi v France , 26 September 1997, §34, Reports 1997-VI; Dalia v France , 19 February 1998, §52, Reports 1998-I; and Boultif v Switzerland , no.54273/00 , §46, ECHR 2001‑IX).
Where immigration is concerned, Article 8 cannot be considered as imposing a general obligation on a State to respect the choice of married couples of the country of their matrimonial residence and to authorise family reunion on its territory (see Gül v Switzerland , 19 February 1996, §38, Reports 1996‑I). However, the removal of a person from a country where close family members are living may amount to an infringement of the right to respect for family life, as guaranteed by Article 8 §1 of the Convention (see Boultif , cited above, §39). Where children are involved, their best interests must be taken into account and national decision-making bodies have a duty to assess evidence in respect of the practicality, feasibility and proportionality of any removal of a non-national parent in order to give effective protection and sufficient weight to the best interests of the children directly affected by it.”
[55] The absorption of nationality issues within article 8 ECHR by the ECtHR has been notably restrained and highly fact specific. Assertions of a right to citizenship have occasionally been recognised as falling within the embrace of respect for private life (as in Genovese v. Malta [2014] 58 EHRR 25). Although the right to acquire a particular nationality is not guaranteed as such by the Convention (see, for example, S.-H. v. Poland [2021] ECHR 381 ) at para [65] as concerns children born through surrogacy), the court has found that an arbitrary refusal of citizenship may, in certain circumstances, raise an issue under article 8 ECHR by impacting on private life (Karassev v. Finland [1999] ECHR 200); Slivenko and Others v. Latvia [2003] ECHR 498.) The loss of citizenship that has already been acquired may entail similar - if not greater - interference with the person’s right to respect for his or her private and family life, as illustrated in Ramadan v. Malta [2017] 65 EHRR 32 , at para [85] (above). Consistent with its rejection of a right to citizenship being protected by article 8 ECHR, the ECtHR has held that article 8 ECHR cannot be construed as guaranteeing, as such, the right to a particular type of residence permit; the choice of permit is in principle a matter for the domestic authorities alone (Kaftailova v Latvia [2007] ECHR 1071 at para [51]).
[56] Arguably the clearest and most consistent theme arising out of this stream of jurisprudence is the ECtHR’s recognition that nationality is an element of a person’s identity. This was stated unambiguously in Ghoumid v France [Application No App 52273/16] at paras [43]–[44]:
“43. Nevertheless, even though the Convention and the Protocols thereto do not guarantee a right to a given nationality as such, any arbitrary deprivation of nationality might in certain circumstances raise an issue under Article 8 of the Convention because of its impact on the private life of the individual (see Ramadan v Malta , no.App 76136/12, §85, 21 June 2016, see also K2 v the United Kingdom (dec.), no.App 42387/13, §45, 7 February 2017). In this connection the court reiterates that nationality is an element of personal identity (see, among other authorities, Mennesson v France , no.App 65192/11, §97, ECHR 2014 (extracts).
44. The court will therefore examine the measures taken against the applicants in the light of their right to respect for their private life. Its supervision will concern two points (see Ramadan , §§86-93, cited above, and K2 , §§50-63, decision cited above). Firstly, it will ascertain whether the measures were arbitrary; it will thus establish whether they were lawful, whether the applicants enjoyed procedural safeguards, and in particular whether they had access to appropriate judicial review, and whether the authorities acted diligently and promptly. Secondly, it will consider the impact of the deprivation of nationality on the applicants’ private life.”
We consider the latter passage to be of particular importance in the context of this appeal.
Article 8 ECHR and the Belfast and British-Irish Agreements
[58] The appellant’s quest to establish that the right which she asserts is protected by article 8 ECHR is based on the Strasbourg decisions considered immediately above. It has the following further dimension. The appellant seeks to rely on those provisions of the two international agreements reproduced in para [15] above, coupled with the relevant Vienna Convention provisions and principles of international law noted in paras [14]–[19]. The question to be addressed is whether these fortify her case that (a) article 8(1) ECHR protects the right which she asserts, (b) sections 1(1) and 12 of the 1981 Act interfere with this right and (c) they do so disproportionately.
[63] Article 31 of the Vienna Convention provides:
“1. A treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.
2. The context for the purpose of the interpretation of a treaty shall comprise, in addition to the text, including its preamble and annexes: (a) any agreement relating to the treaty which was made between all the parties in connection with the conclusion of the treaty; (b) any instrument which was made by one or more parties in connection with the conclusion of the treaty and accepted by the other parties as an instrument related to the treaty.
3. There shall be taken into account, together with the context: 12 (a) any subsequent agreement between the parties regarding the interpretation of the treaty or the application of its provisions; (b) any subsequent practice in the application of the treaty which establishes the agreement of the parties regarding its interpretation; (c) any relevant rules of international law applicable in the relations between the parties. 4. A special meaning shall be given to a term if it is established that the parties so intended.”
We consider the application of these several provisions to be uncomplicated in the present context. First, the words under scrutiny in the two international agreements are to be given their ordinary meaning. Second, we shall take into account the preambles/recitals of both international agreements. Third, we shall consider the two international agreements together. Fourth, we shall have regard to the overarching purposes of the two agreements (which were not a matter of controversy in the arguments of the parties). Finally, we shall not accord any “special meaning” to the words under scrutiny (and none was advanced by either party).
“… This particular portion of the Belfast Agreement does not purport to require new legislation (as several other parts of the Agreement expressly do) ….
Had the provision been intended to require any change to the UK’s domestic legislation on citizenship one would have expected that to have been spelt out and to have been the subject of a clear obligation.”
[68] Finally, on this issue, insofar as the appellant’s reliance on the 1998 international agreements is a thinly veiled attempt to give effect to these unincorporated treaties in domestic law it is doomed to fail. Abundant citation of authority for this fundamental proposition is unnecessary. As the judge noted, this “legal orthodoxy” featured most recently in the decision of the Supreme Court in R (SC) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions [2021] UKSC 26 at paras [76]–[78].
Article 8(2) ECHR: [1] Protection and [2] Interference
“…. The right for which she contends, namely a right not to have renounceable British citizenship conferred upon her.”
As appears particularly from para [18] above, this court was not satisfied that the right asserted by the appellant under article 8 ECHR had been formulated with clarity. This gave rise to a pre-hearing direction and the ensuing formulation set forth in paras [12] and [19] above. From this it follows that the terms of the article 8 ECHR right canvassed before this court differ from those which featured at first instance. In furtherance of the overriding objective and bearing in mind the public law character of these proceedings this court is disposed to permit this reconfiguration of the appellant’s case.
[72] Furthermore, the importance of the status conferred by the legislation under challenge in this appeal, namely British citizenship, has been fully endorsed at the highest judicial level. This has unfolded in the context of challenges to the deprivation of a person’s citizenship and applications for registration as British citizens. In the first of the two decisions in question, Pham v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2015] UKSC 19, the complexity of the legal issues which can materialise in deprivation of citizenship cases and the interaction between domestic nationality laws and international statelessness rules are two of the main themes.
[73] In the second case, R (Project for the Registration of Children as British Citizens) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2022] UKSC 3, Lord Hodge, with whom all members of the court agreed, made the following noteworthy statements about the importance of British citizenship, at paras [26]–[27]:
“There is no dispute as to the importance to an individual of the possession of British citizenship. It gives a right of abode in the UK which is not subject to the qualifications that apply to a non-citizen, including even someone who has indefinite leave to remain. It gives a right to acquire a British passport and thereby a right to come and go without let or hindrance. It can contribute to one’s sense of identity and belonging, assisting people, and not least young people in their sensitive teenage years, to feel part of the wider community. It allows a person to participate in the political life of the local community and the country at large. As the Secretary of State has stated in a guidance document, “Becoming a British citizen is a significant life event. Apart from allowing you to apply for a British Citizen passport, British citizenship gives you the opportunity to participate more fully in the life of your local community.” - Guide T, Registration as a British citizen - a guide for those born in the UK on or after 1 January 1983 who have lived in the UK up to the age of ten (March 2019), Introduction, p 3.
The rights conferred by British citizenship are rights conferred by a process laid down by statute and subordinate legislation and not by the common law. The 1981 Act reformed the basis on which people acquire British citizenship. Entitlement to citizenship by registration arises under the 1981 Act as a result of a connection with the UK as laid down in that Act and compliance with the statutory procedures and conditions. The question raised in this appeal is one of statutory interpretation. The question in short is whether Parliament has authorised in primary legislation the imposition by subordinate legislation of the fees which the appellants challenge.”
[74] The importance of citizenship (or nationality) is also recognised emphatically in the EU legal regime. The right of every national of a Member State to be a citizen of the Union was conferred by the Maastricht Treaty in 1993 i.e. at the highest of the EU law-making levels and is a right which lies at the core of that community of states, being described as “the fundamental status of nationals of the Member States” (see for example the Micheletti case [1992] ECR I-4239 at para [42].)
“According to the practice of States, to arbitral and judicial decisions and to the opinions of writers, nationality is a legal bond having as its basis a social fact of attachment, a genuine connection of existence, interests and sentiments, together with the existence of reciprocal rights and duties. It may be said to constitute the juridical expression of the fact that the individual upon whom it is conferred, either directly by the law or as the result of an act of the authorities, is in fact more closely connected with the population of the state conferring nationality than with that of any other State. Conferred by a State, it only entitles that State to exercise protection vis-à-vis another State, if it constitutes a translation into juridical terms of the individual’s connection with the State which has made him its national.”
The principle of real and effective link has long been recognised in international law and reflected in the practice of many States. The two main principles on which nationality has traditionally been based are descent from a national (jus sanguinis) and birth within a state’s territory (jus soli). These are the typical mechanisms whereby the real and effective link is established. (Brownlee’s Principles of Public International Law, 9th Edition, page 497ff). Notably, each is purely objective.
[83] The right asserted by the appellant which she seeks to fit within the framework of article 8(1) ECHR is formulated as “a right to respect for her status as an Irish citizen only” and “the right to be recognised as an Irish citizen only.” On the assumption that the appellant can lay claim to such a right under article 8(1) ECHR, section 12 of the 1981 Act provides the mechanism for vindicating this right. The activation of the section 12 mechanism would result in the extinguishment of the appellant’s British nationality and the preservation of her Irish nationality exclusively. If the right which she asserts exists, its exercise is not frustrated or impeded by any aspect of section 1 or section 12 of the 1981 Act. Analysed in this way, two consequences follow. First, the real question becomes that of whether the two aforementioned administrative requirements unlawfully interfere with the exercise of the right asserted. Second, the real mischief lies not in the impugned statutory provisions, with the result the appellant’s quest to secure a declaration of incompatibility is defeated on this ground alone.
[84] We return to the particular, developing our analysis in the following way. As demonstrated above, in article 8 ECHR cases involving citizenship issues the ECtHR has focused particularly on the consequences and arbitrariness of the impugned decision or measure. It has not done so in any particular sequence. We shall address firstly the issue of consequences. In the assessment which follows we include, without repeating, para [66] above.
[86] We turn to consider the issue of arbitrariness. It is of obvious significance that the target of the appellant’s challenge consists of two provisions of a measure of primary legislation enacted by a democratically elected parliament legislating in what is universally recognised to be one of the most important areas for every self‑governing state, namely nationality and citizenship. This legislation is now of some 40 years’ vintage and it had certain comparable antecedents. Furthermore, the impugned measures are in conformity with all of the ECtHR touchstones, summarised in Ghoumid v France (see para [56] above): they are in accordance with the law (reposing in primary legislation), access to appropriate judicial review is provided by these proceedings, and there is no suggestion that any relevant authority has failed to act acted diligently and promptly. Finally, it forms no part of the appellant’s case that any particular procedural protections are required and are lacking.
“The Convention is concerned with rights and freedoms which are of real importance in a modern democracy governed by the rule of law. It does not, as is sometimes mistakenly thought, offer relief from ‘the heartache and the thousand natural shocks that flesh is air to.’”
(Procurator Fiscal v Brown [2003] 1 AC 681, per Lord Bingham of Cornhill, p 703. quoting from Shakespeare’s Hamlet.) We further take into account that article 8 ECHR is not a panacea, available to be invoked in the support and protection of the preferences and priorities espoused by every person regarding the conduct and development of every aspect of their private lives.
“Judicial recognition and assertion of the human rights defined in the Convention is not a substitute for the processes of democratic government but a complement to them. While a national court does not accord the margin of appreciation recognised by the European Court as a supra - national court, it will give weight to the decisions of a representative legislature and a democratic government within the discretionary area of judgement accorded to those bodies ….”
This was to become a recurring theme of the subsequent jurisprudence of the House of Lords and Supreme Court. Lord Bingham continued:
“In interpreting the Convention, as any other treaty, it is generally to be assumed that the parties have included the terms which they wished to include and on which they were able to agree, omitting other terms which they did not wish to include or on which they were not able to agree. Thus, particular regard must be had and reliance placed on the express terms of the Convention, which define the rights and freedoms which the contracting parties have undertaken to secure. This does not mean that nothing can be implied into the Convention. The language of the Convention is for the most part so general that some implication of terms is necessary and the case law of the European Court shows that the court has been willing to imply terms into the Convention when it was judged necessary or plainly right to do so. But the process of implication is one to be carried out with caution, if the risk is to be averted that the contracting parties may, by judicial interpretation, become bound by obligations which they did not expressly accept and might not have been willing to accept. As an important constitutional instrument, the Convention is to be seen as a ‘living tree capable of growth and expansion within its natural limits’ …. but those limits will often call for very careful consideration.”
[Emphasis added.]
“The framers of the Convention recognised that it was not only morally right to promote the observance of human rights but that it was also the best way of achieving pluralistic and just societies in which all can peaceably go about their lives. The second aim was to foster effective political democracy. This aim necessarily involves the creation of conditions of stability and order under the rule of law, not for its own sake, but as the best way to ensuring the well-being of the inhabitants of the European countries. After all, democratic government has only one raison d'être, namely to serve the interests of all the people. The inspirers of the European Convention, among whom Winston Churchill played an important role, and the framers of the European Convention, ably assisted by English draftsmen, realised that from time to time the fundamental right of one individual may conflict with the human right of another. Thus, the principles of free speech and privacy may collide. They also realised only too well that a single-minded concentration on the pursuit of fundamental rights of individuals to the exclusion of the interests of the wider public might be subversive of the ideal of tolerant European liberal democracies. The fundamental rights of individuals are of supreme importance but those rights are not unlimited: we live in communities of individuals who also have rights. The direct lineage of this ancient idea is clear: the European Convention (1950) is the descendant of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948) which in article 29 expressly recognised the duties of everyone to the community and the limitation on rights in order to secure and protect respect for the rights of others. It is also noteworthy that article 17 of the European Convention prohibits, among others, individuals from abusing their rights to the detriment of others. Thus, notwithstanding the danger of intolerance towards ideas, the Convention system draws a line which does not accord the protection of free speech to those who propagate racial hatred against minorities: article 10; Jersild v Denmark (1994) 19 EHRR 1, 26, para 31. This is to be contrasted with the categorical language of the First Amendment to the United States Constitution which provides that "Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech." The European Convention requires that where difficult questions arise a balance must be struck. Subject to a limited number of absolute guarantees, the scheme and structure of the Convention reflects this balanced approach. It differs in material respects from other constitutional systems but as a European nation it represents our Bill of Rights. We must be guided by it. And it is a basic premise of the Convention system that only an entirely neutral, impartial, and independent judiciary can carry out the primary task of securing and enforcing Convention rights. This contextual scene is not only directly relevant to the issues arising on the present appeal but may be a matrix in which many challenges under the >Human Rights Act 1998 should be considered.”
Resort to this basic dogma in the speeches of Lord Bingham and Lord Steyn illuminates the path to be pursued by the court in determining this appeal.
[92] Finally, we remind ourselves that the primary purpose, the essential object, of article 8 ECHR is to protect against arbitrary interferences with private and family life, home, and correspondence by a public authority (Libert v. France, at paras [40]-[42]). In the notional balance sheet, the benefits conferred on the appellant by her British citizenship from birth comprehensively outweigh the subtle, imperceptible detriment which she asserts. Of course, the resolution of the appellant’s article 8 ECHR challenge does not entail a box ticking or arithmetical exercise. Rather it behoves the court, having identified the main facts and considerations, to stand back and form an overall evaluative judgement. We have mapped in some detail the path to our conclusion on this discrete issue. A balancing exercise is required. In our judgement this impels inexorably to the conclusion that whether viewed through the lens of a negative or positive right the right asserted by the appellant is not protected by article 8 ECHR. Specifically, the appellant’s case fails to identify any consequences of the operation of the impugned statutory provisions which would warrant a different conclusion or any element of arbitrariness in those provisions.
[93] Given the immediately preceding conclusion the question of whether the impugned measure constitutes an interference with the article 8 ECHR right asserted by the appellant does not arise. If our conclusion that the right which she asserts is not protected by article 8 ECHR is erroneous, our alternative conclusion is that, on the same basis and for the same reasons, no interference is established.
Article 8(2) ECHR: Proportionality
[94] Given these alternative conclusions, no question of justification under article 8(2) ECHR arises. However, on the premise that each of our alternative conclusions is erroneous, we shall examine this issue. As already noted, the appellant accepts that the impugned measure pursues a legitimate aim, namely the protection of the rights and freedoms of others, and is “in accordance with the law.” Accordingly, the sole issue under article 8(2) ECHR is that of proportionality, namely whether it is “necessary in a democratic society.”
[95] We remind ourselves of the contours of the doctrine of proportionality. We do so mindful of the distinction between the doctrine of proportionality in its ECHR context and EU context. This was highlighted by the Supreme Court in R (Lumsdon) v Legal Services Board [2015] UKSC 41. In domestic human rights law the approach to ECHR proportionality has evolved somewhat. It is unnecessary in the present context to trace this evolution, which dates from De Freitas [1999] 1 AC 69 at 80 per Lord Clyde. It suffices, rather, to draw attention to the leading decision of the Supreme Court, Bank Mellat v HM Treasury [2013] UKSC 39. There the entire court was agreed upon the following criteria, at para [74]:
“(1) Whether the objective of the measure is sufficiently important to justify the limitation of a protected right, (2) whether the measure is rationally connected to the objective, (3) whether a less intrusive measure could have been used without unacceptably compromising the achievement of the objective, and (4) whether, balancing the severity of the measure’s effects on the rights of the persons to whom it applies against the importance of the objective, to the extent that the measure will contribute to its achievement, the former outweighs the latter. The first three of these are the criteria listed by Lord Clyde in De Freitas, and the fourth reflects the additional observation made in Huang. I have formulated the fourth criterion in greater detail than Lord Sumption, but there is no difference of substance. In essence, the question at step four is whether the impact of the rights infringement is disproportionate to the likely benefit of the impugned measure.”
[97] Various aspects of the proportionality equation have featured in our consideration of article 8 ECHR protection and interference above. We take into account also the following. First, in the sphere of nationality and citizenship general rules are clearly appropriate in furtherance of coherence, stability, predictability and a workable regime. Second, the impugned statutory provisions promote certainty, predictability and coherence. Third, they perform the important function of avoiding the mischief of statelessness. Fourth, in so doing they achieve conformity with the international legal rules on statelessness and are harmonious with the principle of the common law that parliament is presumed to legislate in a manner compliant with the government’s international legal obligations. Fifth, the conferral of British citizenship on a person at birth does not abrade with that person’s wishes or preferences. It is only at a later stage of development and maturity that a considered, properly informed preference about this matter can be formed. The distinction between neonates and children (on the one hand) and mature teenagers (on the other) seems to us incontestable.
[98] The statutory regime under scrutiny includes the renunciation mechanism of section 12 of the 1981 Act which a person can invoke upon attaining their 18th birthday. This too operates as a general rule. However, it cannot be considered disproportionate on this account per se. The age of 18 is the legal age of majority for every British citizen and it operates as a trigger in various fields and contexts: the legal age of majority for every British citizen is 18, having been reduced from 21 by the Family Law Reform Act 1969 (section 1). Upon attaining 18 everyone is considered to be an adult, thereby acquiring the legal capacity to inter alia enter into legally binding contracts (thus to hold a credit card and take out a loan), to vote in elections, to buy tobacco and cigarettes and have a tattoo. This statutory arrangement is manifestly compatible with the protection of the best interests of children, from neonates to 17 year olds.
[101] A comparable issue arose in R (Williams) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2017] EWCA Civ 98, where a 10 year old boy from a destitute family challenged the requirement to pay a fee of £673 to apply for registration as a British citizen on the basis of ten years continuous residence under section 1(4) of the 1981 Act. The challenge was dismissed. The reasoning of the court is expressed in the main in para [45]:
“What is at root wrong with the argument in the present case is, in my view, this. There is no “fundamental” or “constitutional” right to citizenship registration for persons in the position of the claimant at all. The right is one which Parliament has chosen by statute to create and bestow, in certain specified circumstances. Those circumstances include, as one requirement, an application: which is then required to be accompanied by a fee if it is to be valid. There is nothing in the requirement of a fee to defeat the statutory purpose and intent. On the contrary, it is part of the statutory purpose and intent. Mr Knafler’s argument, with respect, in effect simply subordinates the requirement for a fee-paid application to the other conditions required to be fulfilled if citizenship under section 1(4) of the 1981 Act is to be granted. I can see no sufficient justification for that, having regard to the terms of the statutory scheme.”
[102] There are, by analogy, parallels with high level judicial decisions in both this jurisdiction and that of England and Wales. Illustrations are found in Re Bell [2017] NICA 69 at paras [41]–[43] especially (per Gillen LJ) and R v Cambridge Health Authority, ex parte B [1995] 1 WLR 898 at 906D-F. Decisions such as these give powerful expression to the principle that judgements about the amount to be paid by the citizen for any such service belong to the domain of administrators. Where a court is invited to consider the amount levied the judicial role will inevitably by a restrained one. Judges are not economists or accountants. While they will not flinch from performing their duty in any given case they will do so mindful of these well‑established limitations.
Our Conclusions
[108] We draw together our conclusions in the following way:
(i) The right asserted by the appellant, namely a right to respect for her status as an Irish citizen only, is not protected by article 8 ECHR.
(ii) In the alternative to (i), neither section 1(1) nor section 12 of the British Nationality Act 1981 interferes with this right.
(iii) In the alternative to (i) and (ii), any interference with the appellant’s enjoyment of this right pursues a legitimate aim, is in accordance with the law and is proportionate.
(iv) Section 1(1) of the British Nationality Act 1981, whether on its own or in conjunction with section 12, is harmonious with the rights enshrined in section 1(i) of the Belfast Agreement and Article 1(vi) of the British-Irish Agreement.
[1] i.e. they are 18 years old or, pursuant to s.12(5), have been married or formed a civil partnership.