BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you
consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it
will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free
access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
|
[Home]
[Databases]
[World Law]
[Multidatabase Search]
[Help]
[Feedback]
|
United Kingdom Journals
|
You are here:
BAILII >>
Databases >>
United Kingdom Journals >>
Maclean A, An Alexandrian approach to the knotty problem of wrongful pregnancy: Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust in the House of Lords
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/WebJCLI/2004/issue3/maclean3.html
Cite as:
Maclean A, An Alexandrian approach to the knotty problem of wrongful pregnancy: Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust in the House of Lords
|
[New search]
[Help]
An Alexandrian approach
to the knotty problem of wrongful pregnancy: Rees v Darlington Memorial
Hospital NHS Trust in the House of Lords.
Alasdair Maclean BSc (Hons), MBBS, PGDipLaw, M.Jur
Lecturer in Medical Law
The School of Law
University of Glasgow
Glasgow G12 8QQ
[email protected]
Copyright © Alasdair Maclean, 2004
First published in Web Journal of Current Legal Issues.
Summary
In this commentary, I examine the House of Lords judgment in Rees v Darlington
Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2003] UKHL 52; [2004] 1 AC 309. I briefly summarise the facts and judgments
and then consider the implications both for wrongful pregnancy case law and
suggest that the decision leaves open to challenge the Court of Appeal decision
in Parkinson v St James and Seacroft University Hospital NHS Trust
[2001] EWCA Civ 530; [2001] 3 All ER 97. I also suggest that, although not sufficiently
justified by the majority, their decision to award a conventional sum is justifiable.
I also consider the two more general issues that arise from the case. I briefly
note the unexplicated distinction their Lordships draw between legal and social
policy. I also consider the role that distributive justice has played in the
continuing saga of wrongful pregnancy case law.
Contents
Introduction
The last time a wrongful pregnancy claim reached the House of Lords was in
1999 and the House’s decision caused both consternation and
uncertainty.
(1) In
McFarlane v
Tayside Health Board [2000] 2 AC 59, HL, the pursuers claimed compensation
for the costs arising from the gestation and birth of an unwanted healthy child
conceived as a consequence of the defenders negligence. The House of Lords held
that the McFarlanes could recover general damages for the pain, discomfort and
inconvenience as well as the costs arising out of the pregnancy. However, the
maintenance costs were pure economic loss and not recoverable. Each of their
Lordships delivered different judgments, but if a single principle can be found
it is that making the doctor liable for the costs of raising the child was not
just. Although only made explicit in two of their Lordship’s judgments, it
is arguable that this unifying principle is distributive
justice.
(2)
One of the problems caused by the
McFarlane case was the difficulty
in predicting how the courts would apply the decision when faced with a wrongful
pregnancy case in which the child was born with a disability. The Court of
Appeal in
Parkinson v St James and Seacroft University Hospital NHS Trust
[2001] EWCA Civ 530;
[2001] 3 All ER 97 answered this by allowing
recovery for the additional costs associated with the child’s disability.
Again the decision is analysable in terms of distributive justice and both
Brooke and Hale LJJ relied on the principle. Although some of the judges sitting
in the Court of Appeal were clearly unhappy with the
McFarlane
judgment,
(3) an acceptable status quo
might have been reached were it not for the unpredicted scenario that engendered
the
Rees case.
(4)
The Facts
The claimant in Rees suffered a progressive condition causing
blindness, which made her worry about her ability to look after a child. Because
of this concern, she underwent a sterilisation, which failed. She gave birth to
a healthy child, and the respondents accepted liability for negligence. However,
the High Court case determining the preliminary issue was not heard until after
both the McFarlane and Parkinson judgments. The issue was decided
against the claimant who appealed to the Court of Appeal. By a 2:1 majority, the
Court of Appeal found for the claimant.
The Court of Appeal
Judgments
Hale LJ relied on her ‘deemed equilibrium’ analysis of McFarlane,
which she first constructed in Parkinson. This model treated the McFarlane
decision as creating a balance between the maintenance costs and the benefits
of a healthy child, with each cancelling out the other. This allowed Hale
LJ to argue that anything upsetting that balance and causing additional expense
would allow recovery. In Rees, the mother’s disability created
an additional ‘need’ that tipped the balance: allowing recovery
simply re-established the equilibrium by putting her ‘in the same position
as her able-bodied fellows’ (Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital
NHS Trust [2002] EWCA Civ 88, [23]). Walker LJ rejected the ‘deemed
equilibrium’ model, but allowed recovery, which was ‘fair, just
or reasonable’ and an acceptable extension of the Parkinson decision
(Ibid. at [41]). The dissenting judge, Waller LJ, also rejected the
‘deemed equilibrium’ model and, in a judgment focused on the claimant’s
need, he argued that: ‘On the basis of distributive justice I believe
that ordinary people would think that it was not fair that a disabled person
should recover when mothers who may in effect become disabled by ill-health
through having a healthy child would not’ (Ibid. at [54]).
Top | Contents | Bibliography
The House of Lords
Decision
The Trust appealed and the House of Lords, by a bare majority, allowed the
appeal. Following Lord Millett’s judgment in McFarlane,
the majority argued that the policy arguments in McFarlane retained their
force and it would be unjust to allow recovery for the maintenance costs of a
healthy child whether or not the parent was disabled. Instead, the majority
suggested that the real wrong was the harm done to the mother’s autonomy.
Lord Millett described the loss as the ‘denial of an important aspect
of... personal autonomy, viz the right to limit the size of their family’
(Op cit, at 1129 [123]). Lord Bingham characterised it more precisely. He
stated: ‘To speak of losing the freedom to limit the size of one’s
family is to mask the real loss suffered in a situation of this kind. This is
that a parent, particularly (even today) the mother, has been denied through the
negligence of another, the opportunity to live her life in the way that she
wished and planned’ (Ibid. at 1097 [8]). The majority, therefore,
added what they described as a ‘gloss’ to the McFarlane
judgment and awarded £15,000 in general damages for this infringement of
parental autonomy.
Discussion
This case raises a number of issues, some of which are relevant primarily
to wrongful pregnancy and, by analogy to wrongful birth cases. Other issues have
a more general relevance. There is insufficient space here to go into these
issues in any depth but I will highlight those I believe to be important and I
will indicate the possible implications of the case. I will start with the
issues mainly relevant to wrongful pregnancy.
There were two points on
which all of their Lordships agreed. First, they unanimously rejected Hale
LJ’s ‘deemed equilibrium’:
McFarlane had decided that
the maintenance costs could not be weighed against the benefits flowing from the
birth of a new child, which were impossible to measure. While their Lordships
were correct in rejecting the model as a flawed interpretation of
McFarlane, it had provided a logical explanation of why the extra costs
associated with a disability should be recoverable. Considering the argument
from
McFarlane: the benefits of a new child are immeasurable and the
consequence of this is that they cannot be offset against the maintenance costs.
The House of Lords in
McFarlane concluded from this that, because the
benefits and detriments could not be weighed then the claimants should recover
in full or not at all and it was unjust to allow them to recover in full. Unless
one is prepared to argue that having a disabled child is not - as a matter of
policy - a blessing, which might be interpreted as devaluing the disabled, then
the calculation is no more possible for the birth of a disabled child than it is
for the birth of a healthy child. The costs arising from the disability are
simply additional maintenance costs and, if the detriments cannot be weighed
against the benefits then simply increasing the detriments cannot change that:
if x cannot be balanced against y then nor can x be balanced against y + z.
The problem with the rejection of the deemed equilibrium is demonstrated
by Lord Hope’s argument. After emphasising that the benefits and burdens
of a disabled child are as entangled as those of a healthy child, while
acknowledging the extra costs associated with a disability, but being committed
to rejecting the deemed equilibrium, Lord Hope is left without any justification
for allowing the additional costs. His response is to argue that, instead of an
‘equilibrium’ there was ‘an element of symmetry... inherent in
the exercise... [which] lies in the assumption that the parent and the child are
both normal and healthy ’ (
Ibid. at 1110-1111 [60]). This argument
has the air of sophistry and it is submitted that, in this context,
‘equilibrium’ and ‘symmetry’ are synonymous and Lord
Hope’s argument should be rejected.
The second point of agreement
was that the
McFarlane judgment was correct and, even had they thought
otherwise, it would be wrong to overturn such a recent decision of a differently
constituted House.
(5) In
Rees,
Lord Steyn characterised the ratio of
McFarlane as reliant on the
impossibility of weighing the benefits and detriments of the birth of a healthy
child, and Lord Millett’s point that it would be ‘morally
offensive’ for society ‘to regard a normal healthy child as more
trouble and expense than it is worth’. When coupled with the principle of
distributive justice, or the ‘fair, just or reasonable’ test –
which is arguably just distributive justice by another name – the result
was that the maintenance costs of a healthy child could not be recovered
(
Ibid. at 1102 [28-29]). In
McFarlane, Lord Steyn determined the
distributive justice argument by reference to the supposed view of the traveller
on the Underground (
Op cit, at 82). It is impossible from this to
determine the exact end point by which a fair distribution should be measured.
However, it is arguable that the subsequent Court of Appeal hearings of
Parkinson and
Rees were determined on the basis of
need.
(6) This reliance on a
needs-based distributive justice argument has been undermined by the
majority’s decision in
Rees, which applies in all cases where the
child is healthy. If that point is considered in conjunction with the previous
argument about the lack of balance to be tipped by the extra costs arising from
a disability, it is arguable that parents should no longer be able to recover
where the child is disabled. Certainly, Lords Bingham, Nicholls and Scott argued
that the award of a conventional sum was equally appropriate in the case of a
disabled child (
Op cit, at 1097, 1099, 1135 [9, 18, 145]), but Lord
Millett’s judgment was unclear on the issue. Since the point is
obiter to the decision, their Lordships’ arguments are not
determinative and the Court of Appeal remains free to follow
Parkinson.
(7) However, should
they do so, the defendants may well feel that they have good grounds for appeal
thus encouraging further litigation.
Rees also opens up the
question of whether those cases in which the purpose of the medical intervention
(sterilisation or abortion) was specifically intended to avoid the birth of a
disabled child should be decided differently (
Ibid. at 1135 [145] per
Lord Scott). Mason (2002) argues that, in these wrongful birth cases, where the
woman is specifically seeking to avoid the birth of a disabled child, there is a
greater proximity between the doctor and the costs arising from the disability.
However, the principle of distributive justice, rather than the issue of
proximity, has determined the wrongful pregnancy cases. Because many of the same
distributive arguments will be relevant, even if it is argued that greater
proximity acts as a counterweight to the principles of distributive justice, the
issue of recovery in wrongful birth cases has at least been reopened by
Rees.
The final point that is primarily relevant to wrongful
pregnancy cases, but which may have implications for other cases where the wrong
may be characterised as an infringement of autonomy, was the majority’s
decision to award a conventional sum in general damages as recognition of that
wrong. The dissenting judges rejected this and both Lords Steyn and Hope devoted
a significant part of their judgments to present a powerful criticism of the
decision. Lord Steyn argued that the award of a conventional sum was not a
‘gloss’ on
McFarlane but a ‘radical and most important
development which should only be embarked on after rigorous examination of
competing arguments’. The majority provided no authority for the award, it
had been implicitly rejected by the majority in
McFarlane, there had been
no opportunity for the lower courts to consider such an approach and it was
beyond the ‘limits of permissible creativity for judges’ that was a
‘backdoor evasion of the legal policy enunciated in
McFarlane’ and was, therefore, the remit of Parliament and not the
courts (
Ibid. at 1107-1108 [40-47]). Lord Hope agreed with Lord Steyn,
adding that describing the freedom to restrict the size of one’s family as
a right begged many questions and awarding damages without the aim of returning
the injured party to their pre-tort position undermined the general aim of tort
law.
Because of these and other problems with such an award, it was a
development that was ‘hugely controversial’ and should be left to
Parliament (
Ibid. at 1114-1116 [73-77]).
It is submitted that this
criticism is undeserved and was, perhaps, a consequence of the tangled knot that
had resulted from the initially intuitive use of distributive justice. While
the Court of Appeal judges were well intentioned in their attempt to alleviate
the harshness of
McFarlane, their use of distributive justice simply gave
the decisions an air of arbitrariness, which was highlighted by Waller
LJ’s dissenting judgment in the Court of Appeal hearing of
Rees and
noted in the House of Lords. Lord Steyn, for example, acknowledged that: that
‘there is an element of arbitrariness involved in holding that only the
disabled mother of a healthy and normal child can claim damages’
(
Ibid. at 1105 [38]). Despite noting that ‘it is of prime
importance that the law avoid arbitrariness’ he was ‘persuaded that
the injustice of denying to such a seriously disabled mother the limited remedy
of the extra costs’ (
Ibid. at 1105-1106 [38-39]). If avoiding an
arbitrary law is of ‘prime importance’, it must at least be arguable
that it is preferable to maintain a system of formal justice in which everyone
knows where they stand and the law is predictable, rather than to develop an
uncertain system in which individual decisions depend explicitly on the
prejudiced intuitions of the judge. The
McFarlane judgment, however, was
harsh and arguably unfair on the parents. It is understandable, therefore, that
seeing a wrong committed with the consequential harm going entirely
uncompensated would cause their Lordships to raise Alexander’s sword and
cleave the Gordian knot tied with the rope of distributive justice.
The
majority’s bold stroke, while understandable, is still open to the
criticism that it was an illegitimate step for their Lordships to take. Lord
Steyn’s point that it was beyond the ‘permissible creativity’
of a judge may be difficult to entirely rebuke given that it is a matter of
degree and there is no clear line marking the boundary between what is
permissible and what is forbidden. However, there are a number of reasons that
would support an argument that the move was acceptable. To begin with, the award
of general damages itself is accepted as reasonable and may be granted to
compensate for the ‘diminution of value’ resulting from a
‘loss of amenity’. Such an award is available at the top of the
scale to permanently unconscious claimants. While the Law Commission was against
such an award they recommended retaining it because of the level of support
received from respondents (1998 p
6-9).
(8) One of the main reasons
underlying the support was the: ‘unconscious victim’s complete loss
of amenity’, and ‘[f]ailure to recognise this would be to undervalue
and trivialise their experiences’(
Ibid. p 7, para.
2.23).
Although loss of amenity is not synonymous with loss of autonomy,
because autonomy may enhance or enable enjoyment of life, loss of autonomy is
subsumed by loss of amenity. Thus, English law already recognises a diminution
of autonomy as a suitable basis for the award of a conventional sum. If this
argument is not accepted then consider the relevance of the Human Rights Act
1998 (HRA). This Act effectively incorporates the European Convention on Human
Rights and Article 8 of this Convention protects the individual’s right to
a private and family life. It is not particularly contentious to argue that this
would include the right to determine the size of one’s own family,
constrained - of course – by nature’s generosity. Since, under s
6(1)-(3), the courts are supposed to develop the law in accordance with the HRA
(Wadham et al 2003, p 12), any infringement of a protected right should be
compensated irrespective of whether the complaint involves a pleaded breach of
the HRA. In
Cornelius v De Taranto[2001] EMLR 12, 329 (at 344, [66]) for
example, the court held that damages for a breach of confidence should be more
than nominal because it involved a protected
right.
(9) Thus, it is submitted that,
even though the justification for a conventional sum was not fully explicated,
it is a defensible award.
If the legal rule determined by
McFarlane is that no award of damages may be made to cover the
maintenance costs of a healthy child then the award of a conventional sum for
loss of autonomy is not precluded. Calling it a ‘gloss’ may be an
understatement, but it is a smaller step than the arbitrary award to cover the
costs arising from the parent’s disability. The beauty of such an award is
that it makes no unjustly arbitrary distinction between the claimants, all of
whom will receive the same award. It will also make it considerably easier to
come to an out of court settlement since there will be no need to haggle over
the projected expenses of raising a child or the impact of a disability on those
costs. It is, however, a bold but risky strategy. It is bold because, with one
stroke, it destroys the knotty tangle weaved by the courts’ ill-considered
use of distributive justice. It is risky because it may end up pleasing no one,
except perhaps the NHS. Given the potential costs involved in raising a child,
the parents of a healthy child may still feel hard done by. Disabled parents may
feel aggrieved because the comparatively small award is unlikely to meet the
additional costs incurred because of their disability. Those in favour of a full
award in line with corrective justice principles may feel that the solution
fails to do justice and those who believe
McFarlane was a wholly just
decision may feel that the judgment has been
undermined.
(10)The case
raises two issues of more general interest. First, their Lordships explicitly
referred to a reliance on ‘legal policy’, which they differentiated
from ‘social policy’: it being legitimate for the courts to rely on
legal policy but not social policy. This is intriguing because, in
Rees,
four of their Lordships argued that the decision in
McFarlane relied on
legal policy (
Op cit at 1095 [6] per Lord Bingham; 1102 [29] per Lord
Steyn; 1109 [52] per Lord Hope; 1124 [105] per Lord
Millett).
(11) However, in
McFarlane, only Lord Millett explicitly referred to ‘legal
policy’, while the others either shied away from policy or denied its
relevance. Lord Millett rather unhelpfully explained that (
Op cit at
108):
Legal policy... is not the same as public policy, even though moral
considerations may play a part in both. The court is engaged in a search for
justice, and this demands that the dispute be resolved in a way which is fair
and reasonable and accords with ordinary notions of what is fit and proper.
Although it is important to examine the concept of legal policy in more
detail, I intend to explore this in another article, and space does not permit a
full consideration at this point.
The final issue is the relevance and application of distributive justice in
tort law, which is primarily a system of corrective justice. Following on from
the use of distributive justice to deny recovery in
White v Chief Constable
of South Yorkshire Police[1999] 2 AC 455 (per Lords Hoffmann,
Browne-Wilkinson and Steyn), Lord Steyn again explicitly relied on that
principle to deny recovery in
McFarlane (
Op cit at 82-83). Lord
Hope also referred to distributive justice as a limiting principle, while Lord
Slynn relied on the
Caparo v Dickman [1990] 2 AC 605 duty-criterion that
it was ‘fair, just or reasonable, which is arguably distributive justice
by another name.
(12) It may also be
argued that both Lord Millett’s and Lord Clyde’s judgment were
informed by ideas of distributive justice, although neither make explicit
reference to the principle. In the subsequent Court of Appeal cases,
distributive justice arguments are relied on to allow recovery, in
Parkinson (
Op cit e.g. at 104 per Brooke LJ), where the child was
disabled, and in the Court of Appeal hearing of
Rees (
Op cit at
[22] per Hale LJ), where it is the parent who was disabled. The principle was
again relied on – although not always explicitly - by the minority in the
House of Lords hearing of
Rees, to argue that the disabled parent should
recover for the additional costs. In fact, six of the seven judges constructed
arguments around distributive justice or the effectively synonymous ‘fair,
just or reasonable’ criterion (
Op cit at 1095, 1098, 1102, 1111,
1122, 1129 [6, 13, 29, 63, 97, 121].
While it is arguable that a system of corrective justice is predicated
on distributive justice principles applied to outcome responsibility
(Honoré 1995 at 83), using those principles to limit the application of
corrective justice, once that system is established, requires further
justification. Space precludes a full discussion of these
issues,
(13) however, it is arguable
that any limitation of liability is analysable in terms of distributive justice.
Furthermore, the ‘fair, just or reasonable’ criterion, which has
become an accepted part of English
law,
(14) is now being acknowledged
as expressing distributive justice principles. Since limiting liability has long
been a part of deciding cases in tort, it is more open of the judges to refer
explicitly to distributive justice. This openness has exposed some of the
difficulties in applying such a general principle to specific cases. Perhaps the
biggest problem is in determining the endpoint used to decide whether the
particular distribution is fair. In
McFarlane, Lord Steyn clouds the
issue by appealing to the moral intuition of the traveller on the Underground
(
Op cit, at 82). In the Court of Appeal, especially Hale LJ’s
judgments, the endpoint appears to be based on
need.
(15) The trouble with reliance
on need is that it would also support recovery because the parents are socially
disadvantaged. This is recognised by Waller LJ, the dissenting judge in the
Court of Appeal hearing of Rees (
Op cit, at [53-55]).
In the House of Lords, the minority - who would have allowed recovery where
the parent is disabled - acknowledged the strength of Waller LJ’s arguments
and even recognised that to allow recovery in the present case would create
an arbitrary law. The minority felt, however, that such arbitrariness was a
price worth paying for the possibility of justice in this case (
Op cit,
at 1111 [61] per Lord Hope; 1105-1107 [38-39] per Lord Steyn). An arbitrary
law, however, is an unjust law and the minority’s approach would sacrifice
formal justice for arbitrary satisfaction of substantive justice. For Lord Millett,
this approach was ‘destructive of the concept of distributive justice’
(
Op cit, at 1128-1129 [121-122]).
(16)
This unhappy state of affairs, which is solved by the majority’s Alexandrian
sword stroke, is caused by the inconsistent and ill-thought-out reliance on
distributive justice. If applied consistently with
McFarlane, the principle
would arguably result in recovery being denied in all wrongful pregnancy (and
perhaps wrongful birth) cases, irrespective of any disability. If applied consistently
with the Court of Appeals’ approach then
McFarlane is undermined
and the court is forced to adopt the role of a benefits agency. The point here
is not that the courts are necessarily wrong to turn to distributive justice
when trying to fairly apply principles of corrective justice, but that if such
an appeal is made then it must be applied consistently and coherently, which
requires a far more rigorous approach than the judges have taken.
Top | Contents | Bibliography
Conclusion
In Rees, the majority in the House of Lords cleaved the Gordian knot
created by the use of distributive justice in the previous wrongful pregnancy
cases. The knot was the consequence of the judges manipulating the principle
in order to justify their intuitive judgments and was exacerbated by the constraints
on the Court of Appeal arising from McFarlane. The majority’s
decision, to award a conventional sum for the harm done to the claimant’s
autonomy, was insufficiently explained by their Lordships. However, as I have
argued, their approach is capable of justification, although the decision
itself, while softening the potential harshness of McFarlane, risks
not pleasing anyone.
Rees is important, both for the limited area of wrongful pregnancy/birth
and for its wider implications for tort law more generally. As far as wrongful
pregnancy is concerned, the case reopens the issue of whether recovery will
be allowed for the extra costs associated with the care of a disabled child.
The majority’s decision throws into doubt the Court of Appeal’s
decision in Parkinson. While that case has not been overturned it is
certainly open to challenge and the spectre of another House of Lords case
looms large. This uncertainty also extends to the wrongful birth cases.
The wider implications of the case concern the meaning and use of legal policy
and the ever more explicit reliance on an insufficiently explicated and inconsistently
interpreted principle of distributive justice. While reliance on this principle
may be necessary if tort liability is to be limited, and while the greater
openness of making explicit this reliance is laudable, use of distributive
justice in this way needs to be subject to more critical intellectual rigour
if it is to allow the development of a just law that is predictable because
it is both coherent and consistent.
Top | Contents
Bibliography
J.E. Cameron-Perry, ‘Return of the burden of the
“blessing”’ (1999) 149 NLJ 1887
T. Honoré,
‘The Morality of Tort Law – Questions and Answers’ in: D.G.
Owen (ed.) (1995)
Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Oxford:
Clarendon Press) 73
The Law Commission Report No 257
Damages for Personal
Injury: Non-Pecuniary Loss (1998). Available at:
http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/files/lc257.pdf
(Accessed 20th November 2003).
A.R. Maclean, ‘
McFarlane v
Tayside Health Board: A Wrongful
Conception in the House of Lords’ [2000] 3 Web JCLI, available at:
http://webjcli.ncl.ac.uk/2000/issue3/maclean3.html
(accessed 25 November 2003)
J.K.Mason ‘Wrongful Pregnancy, Wrongful
Birth and Wrongful Terminology’ (2002) 6
Edinburgh Law Review
46.
R. Mullender, ‘Corrective justice, distributive justice, and the law
of negligence’ (2001) 17(1) Professional Negligence 35.
J.
Wadham, H. Mountfield, A. Edmunds, (3rd Edition, 2003)
Blackstone’s Guide to the Human Rights Act 1998 (Oxford:
Blackstone’s Press).
Endnotes
(1) See, Maclean, A.R.
‘McFarlane v Tayside Health Board: A Wrongful Conception in the House of
Lords’ (2000) 3 WJCLI, available at:
http://webjcli.ncl.ac.uk/2000/issue3/maclean3.html
(accessed 25 November 2003); Cameron-Perry, JE ‘Return of the burden of
the “blessing”’ (1999) 149 NLJ
1887.
(2) McFarlane v Tayside Health
Board [2000] 2 AC 59 at 82-84 per Lord Steyn; and at 96 per Lord Hope. Lord
Slynn (at 76) relied on the ‘fair, just and reasonable’ test, which
is perhaps simply an implicit appeal to distributive justice. Note that Lord
Millett has also argued that the ‘fair, just or reasonable’ test
‘expresses the same idea’ as distributive justice:
Rees v Darlington
Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2004] 1 AC 309, 344 [105].
(3) Hale LJ’s
attitude is apparent from her judgments in
Parkinson v St James and Seacroft
University Hospital [2001] EWCA Civ 530;
[2001] 3 All ER 97, and the Court
of Appeal hearing of
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2002] EWCA Civ 88, CA.
(4) See Lord
Steyn’s comment in
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust
[2004] 1 AC 309, 325 [36].
(5)
See, for example, Lord Millett’s judgment:
Rees v Darlington Memorial
Hospital NHS Trust [2004] 1 AC 309, 343
[102-103].
(6) See, for example,
Hale LJ’s argument in,
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS
Trust [2002] EWCA Civ 88,
[22].
(7) See also Douglas, G.
‘
Rees v
Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2003] UKHL 52’ (2004) 34 Fam. Law 22, at
23.
(8) Such an award had been
approved by the House of Lords in
West v Shephard [1964] AC 326.
(9) This aspect of the case
was upheld on appeal without comment:
(2002) 68 BMLR 62,
CA.
(10) Lord Steyn referred to the
award as ‘a backdoor evasion of the legal policy enunciated in
McFarlane’:
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2004] 1 AC 309, 328
[46].
(11) See Lord Hope’s
comment in
McFarlane v Tayside Health Board [2000] 2 AC 59 at 95 where he
states that: ‘If the law is unsatisfactory, the remedy lies in the hands
of the legislature’; see also Lord Clyde at
100.
(12) See
McFarlane v
Tayside Health Board [2000] 2 AC 59 at 76 per Lord Slynn; and at 96 per Lord
Hope. Note that Lord Millett has also argued that the ‘fair, just or
reasonable’ test ‘expresses the same idea’ as distributive
justice:
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2004] 1 AC 309,
at 344 [105].
(13) For just such
a discussion, see: Mullender, R. ‘Corrective justice, distributive
justice, and the law of negligence’ (2001) 17(1)
Professional
Negligence 35.
(14) This is
not true in Australian law, which has rejected the
Caparo test:
Melchior v Cattanach [2003] HCA 38, at [121-122] per Kirby
J.
(15) See, e.g.
Parkinson v
St James and Seacroft University Hospital [2001] 3 All ER 97 at 125; and
Rees v Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust [2002] EWCA Civ 88,
[22].
(16) Lord Millett’s
comment was directed at the Court of Appeal’s decision but is equally
applicable to the minority’s judgments in the House of
Lords.
BAILII:
Copyright Policy |
Disclaimers |
Privacy Policy |
Feedback |
Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/WebJCLI/2004/issue3/maclean3.html